Discussion
The Pursuit of Perfection: A
Conversation on the Ethics of Genetic Engineering
Wednesday, March 31, 2004
3:00 5:00 p.m.
The
Brookings Institution, Falk Auditorium
1775 Massachusetts Aveune, NW,
Washington, D.C.
Reception following, Zilkha Lounge, 5:00 - 6:30
p.m.
"Breakthroughs in genetics present us with a promise and a
predicament," Michael Sandel writes in the April 2004 cover story of The
Atlantic Monthly. "The promise is that we may soon be able to treat and
prevent a host of debilitating diseases. The predicament is that our
newfound genetic knowledge may also enable us to manipulate our own
natureto enhance our muscles, memories, and moods; to choose the sex,
height, and other genetic traits of our children; to make ourselves
'better than well.'"
As a range of performance-enhancing therapies
becomes a scientific reality, we confront a new world in which human
beings wield increasing power over their destinies. But to what end? What
assumptions drive this quest for perfectionand what are the potential
costs? The Pew Forum on Religion and Public Life and The Brookings
Institution invite you to a discussion of the moral considerations that
inform the debate about genetic engineering, enhancement and the quest for
perfection.
Featuring:
Michael Sandel,
Anne T. and Robert M. Bass Professor of Government, Harvard University;
member, President's Council on Bioethics; author of "The Case Against
Perfection," The Atlantic Monthly, April 2004
Responding:
Lee M. Silver, Professor
at Princeton University in the Department of Molecular Biology and the
Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International Affairs; author of
Remaking Eden: How Genetic Engineering and Cloning Will Transform the
American Family
Moderating:
E.J. Dionne,
Jr., Co-Chair, Pew Forum; Senior Fellow, The Brookings Institution
LUIS LUGO: Good
afternoon and thank you all for coming. You're braver than those who were
deterred by just a little bit of sprinkling out there. We're delighted
that you are here.
My name is Luis Lugo and I am the director of
the Pew Forum on Religion and Public Life. The Forum is a non-partisan
organization, and we do not take positions on policy debates, including
the one you're about to hear today.
It is my pleasure to welcome
you this afternoon to "The Pursuit of Perfection: A Conversation on the
Ethics of Genetic Engineering." We are very pleased to be cosponsoring
this event with our friends here at the Brookings Institution, and I want
to, in particular, thank the communications staff here who has been so
helpful in working with us and putting this event together and bringing it
to you.
We are here today to talk about dare I say it? a brave
new world. As a growing number of performance enhancing technologies
become a practical reality, we confront a new world in which human beings
wield increasing power over their own destinies. But to what end? And what
are the assumptions that guide this quest for perfection? And at the end
of the day, will the benefits outweigh the costs?
We are very
fortunate to have with us today two of the leading experts in this field
to offer us a window into the possible futures, futures which may be
scary, may be hopeful, but which are in any case much nearer than most of
us realize.
Now, before I turn things over to the moderator, I do
want to acknowledge another Pew funded project that is very much involved
in this area of work. The Genetics and Public Policy Center, which is
taking the lead in understanding the technologies involved in genetic
engineering, assessing public and stakeholder sentiment towards them and
evaluating the current legal and political landscape in order to craft
policy options that will help guide the development and use of genetic
technologies. We are pleased that Joan Scott, the deputy director of the
Center, could join us today. Joan, if you could please stand so everyone
takes a look at you? Thank you so much. Pleasure to have you.
I
will now hand things over to my good colleague, E.J. Dionne, who is a
senior fellow here at the Brookings Institution, a columnist for The
Washington Post, a professor at Georgetown, and co-chair of the Pew Forum
on Religion and Public Life. He will be introducing our speakers and
moderating the discussion today.
E.J.
E.J. DIONNE, JR.:
Thank you very much, Luis.
"When science moves faster than moral
understanding, as it does today, men and women struggle to articulate
their unease." That's what Mike Sandel writes in the first paragraph of
this excellent piece in The Atlantic, "The Case Against Perfection." I
want to thank The Atlantic for publishing Mike and helping make this event
possible and also for all their help with it.
I must say for me
this is a particularly exciting moment. I have been a Mike Sandel fan for
a very long time, and it's like a Red Sox fan getting to introduce Nomar
Garciaparra; if there are any Yankees fans in the audience, I don't
apologize for that.
MR. LUGO: E.J., we're bipartisan here
(inaudible)
MR. DIONNE: These are purely my own views and do not
represent the views of the Pew Forum, which probably does not want to
connect itself in any way to my baseball team. (Laughter)
Many of
you in this room have worked with Mike or know his work. I was just
looking this morning at some of the reviews of his book Democracy's
Discontent, and every adjective you would want has been applied to that
book. "A profound contribution to our understanding of the present
discontent," said the Wall Street Journal. "One of the most powerful works
of political philosophy in recent years," said Fouad Ajami in U.S. News
and World Report. Moving from right to left, George Will called the book,
"Wonderful." John Judas called it, "An important book that inspires." And
that's what Mike Sandel does, and he does it without pandering or
trimming.
Indeed, there was a politician who ran under the slogan,
"He never ducks the tough ones" the politician used that slogan because
our notion somehow is politicians like to duck the tough ones. As you will
hear today, Mike Sandel seeks out the tough ones and tries to help us
understand.
We are also so grateful that Lee Silver, Professor of
Molecular Biology and Public Affairs at the Woodrow Wilson School at
Princeton, has joined us today. I couldn't imagine a better combination to
discuss this subject today.
We also have many distinguished
bioethicists in the audience. I'd like to welcome Janet Rowley who's a
member of the President's Council on Bioethics, who's with us today, and
also Dean Clancy and Yuval Levin who are the executive director and the
deputy executive director of the Council.
Let me introduce Mike.
He is the Anne T. and Robert M. Bass Professor of Government at Harvard
University where he teaches both graduate and undergraduate courses in
contemporary philosophy, including Ethics and Biotechnology; Markets,
Morals and Law; and Globalization and His Discontents. His courses are so
popular that Harvard actually thought of moving them to Fenway Park. He
also serves on the President's Council on Bioethics. He has received
fellowships from the Carnegie Corporation, the Ford Foundation, the
American Council of Learned Societies and the National Endowment for the
Humanities. His publications include Liberalism and the Limits of Justice,
Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy and
Liberalism and Its Critics.
Lee Silver is a Professor of Molecular
Biology and Public Affairs at the Woodrow Wilson School of Public and
International Affairs at Princeton University. He has been elected to the
governing boards of the Genetics Society of America and the International
Mammalian Genome Society. He is a fellow of the American Association for
the Advancement of Science. He was a member of the New Jersey Bioethics
Commission Taskforce, formed to recommend reproductive policy positions
for the state legislature in New Jersey. He has testified frequently
before Congress and state legislatures. He is the recipient of National
Institute of Health grants on evolution and genetics. He is the author of
this is a wonderful title, as well Remaking Eden: How Genetic
Engineering and Cloning Will Transform the American Family, and Mouse
Genetics: Concepts and Practice (which was not published by the Disney
Corporation).
It is so great to have you both here. Michael,
welcome to Brookings.
(Applause.)
MICHAEL
SANDEL: Well, thank you, E.J., very much. I want to begin by thanking
E.J., who is a friend of long standing and someone whose work in
journalism and academia and public life shaping our public arguments I
very much admire. And he's a good friend. I also want to thank Luis Lugo
very much for the role of the Pew Forum in convening us here and Professor
Silver for being willing to come and join in this discussion.
E.J.
mentioned that I'm a member of the President's Council on Bioethics, so I
want to hasten to add that I'm speaking here only for myself and not on
behalf of the President's Council. He mentioned I suppose following his
introduction, I should say, too, I'm a Red Sox fan, and I don't speak for
the Red Sox for that matter.
The topic of genetic engineering and
enhancement as public policy forums go is admittedly an arcane, even
rarified subject. I've only just begun to learn about genetic engineering,
largely through my being confronted with some of these questions, as we
all have been, on the President's Council. What drew me to the subject
beyond the intrinsic interest of the question of remaking or reengineering
ourselves and our nature is that it forces us to think about some big
questions, questions even bigger than genetics and genetic enhancement,
questions that really go to the terms of political discourse, questions
that go to the way we conceive our public philosophy or a public ethic.
And while I will try to lay out an argument here about genetic
engineering, I want to do it in a way that at least invites us to have a
discussion about those bigger questions of our reigning public ethic.
Just to start from people's gut level reactions to news of genetic
enhancement: Most people find at least some forms of genetic engineering
disquieting, but it's not easy to articulate the source of our unease.
It's not easy to explain exactly what it is that we find troubling about
it. That fact has something to do, it seems to me, with the terms in which
we think about morality, ethics and politics. In order to grapple with the
ethics of enhancement, we have to confront big questions, but old
questions, questions largely lost from view these days, questions about
the moral status of nature and about the proper stance of human beings
toward the given world. So this is the way in which, trying to figure out
what it is that troubles us about this or that instance of genetic
enhancement, makes us confront these bigger, older questions.
And
it ultimately or this is what I'm going to try to propose it
challenges us to re-examine a dominant impulse of our public philosophy,
which has very much to do, across the political spectrum, with a vision of
freedom bound up with mastery, dominion and control. That's an abstract
idea, so I'd like to work up to it gradually, first by considering four
very concrete examples of enhancement that are either available now and
practiced or on the horizon.
First, muscles. Researchers have
developed a synthetic gene that when injected into the muscle cells of
mice makes muscles grow and prevents them from deteriorating with age. So
the question arises, should this become possible in human beings? What are
the proper uses of genetic alteration of muscles? Should it just be to
cure muscular dystrophy and the atrophy of muscles that comes with age? Or
should athletes be able to use it to bulk up without steroids?
Now, usually when we think about steroids in sports or other forms
of enhancement, the first objections that spring to mind have to do with
two things. One is safety steroids are unsafe, they carry long-term
health risks. The other is fairness. Is it a kind of cheating? Suppose for
the sake of argument that muscle enhancement were safe. What about the
fairness argument? Well, some people might say a genetically altered
athlete would have an unfair competitive advantage, but the fairness
argument isn't decisive. It's not decisive because it's always been the
case that some athletes are better endowed genetically than others. We
don't consider the natural inequality of genetic endowments to undermine
the fairness of sports. So what would be the difference if genetically
altered athletes were to compete?
If genetic enhancement in sports
is morally objectionable, in other words, it must be for some reason other
than safety and other than fairness, because if it were safe in principle
it could be made available to anyone who wanted to use it and the fairness
objection would fall away.
Second example: memory. Researchers are
now able to produce smart mice by inserting extra copies of the memory
related gene into mouse embryos. Now, human memory is much more complex,
but there are biotech companies now in hot pursuit of memory enhancing
drugs or cognition enhancers. They're aiming at not only the market of
those who lose memory due to Alzheimer's, but also the many millions of
baby boomers who are beginning to experience age-related memory loss. If
they could come up with a cognition enhancer of the kind they're seeking,
it would be a bonanza for the pharmaceutical industry, a Viagra for the
brain.
What about that? Would that be objectionable? Let's assume
for the sake of argument it could be done safely. What about fairness?
Some might worry, Well, this will be expensive, won't it? And won't that
mean that it'll exacerbate the gap between rich and poor? If you're
wealthy, you'll be able to afford cognition enhancement, and if you're
not, you won't.
And there is a point to that worry, but it's not
the fundamental worry. Think about it: Why would that scenario be
objectionable? Would it be objectionable because the unenhanced poor would
be denied the benefits of bioengineering their memories? Or because the
enhanced affluent are somehow dehumanized by going in for this? So the
first question, the fairness objection, is a real objection, but it's not
the first, not the most fundamental question about these technologies. The
fundamental question is not how to assure equal access to the thing, but
whether we should aspire to it in the first place.
We can see this
by considering the third example that's already available: height
enhancement through the use of human growth hormone. Since the '80s this
hormone has been approved by the FDA for abnormally short children who
suffer from hormone deficiencies or other illnesses. But parents of short
but otherwise healthy kids come along and say, Why not for our kids, too?
They suffer taunting on the playground. Why can't they be taller? It's
true they're not ill. They just have short parents. And the FDA wrestled
with this, and this summer the Eli Lilly pharmaceutical company persuaded
the FDA to approve its human growth hormone for healthy children whose
projected adult height would be in the bottom one percentile.
That
immediately raises the broader ethical question. Why not other short
children? Why only very, very short ones? And for that matter, why
shouldn't it be available to all children? There might be those who are
average or above average in height who want to be even taller. Maybe they
want to make the basketball team. Is there anything wrong in principle
with height enhancement through the use of growth hormone cosmetic
height enhancement; that is to say, not connected with any underlying
medical illness or ailment?
Well, some might say, Yeah, there's
something we're not quite comfortable with about that prospect. But what
is it? Maybe it's fairness or a related thing. Height enhancement, if you
imagine this going on, motoring along on a large scale, would ultimately
be collectively self-defeating. As some people become taller, others
become shorter relative to the norm, and so as the unenhanced begin to
feel shorter, what would they do? They might, if they care about it, begin
to seek treatment, and then there'd be a kind of hormonal arms race. That
would leave everyone worse off, especially those this is the fairness
worry who can't afford to buy their way up from shortness.
But
here, too, the fairness objection doesn't really get at what's worrying
about this. If we were bothered only by the injustice of adding shortness
to the problems of the poor, we could remedy that unfairness by providing
publicly subsidized height enhancements. So the real question is not
fairness, is not access those are serious questions the prior question
is whether we want to live in a society where parents feel compelled to
spend a fortune and this is not cheap, this height enhancement to make
perfectly healthy kids a few inches taller.
One last example
before delving into an objection that lies and projects us beyond safety
and beyond fairness: sex selection. It's now possible to go to a clinic in
Fairfax, Virginia, and select in advance the sex of our your child. They
are ways of doing it through embryo screening and pre-implementation
genetic diagnosis, but this company in Fairfax, Virginia, can do it by
sperm sorting. They have a machine that sorts sperm and separates
y-bearing sperm that would produce a boy from the x-bearing sperm that
would produce girls. It's a flowcytometer, this machine, and it's pretty
successful, 81 percent success rate for girls, 76 for boys. The technology
is called, quaintly, MicroSort, and they licensed it from the U.S.
Department of Agriculture, which developed it for breeding cattle. Now you
can use it to select the sex of your child.
What about this? Is
that fine? Do you like that idea? Maybe everybody does. But insofar as
people are uneasy about this, what would be the objection? One obvious
objection is people might worry about sex discrimination. If you look at
some societies around the world India, China, for example there has
been in the last 15 years a huge skewing of sex ratios, where the ratio of
boys to girls is 120 to 100 in northern India in some places, 140 to
100.
For the sake of this exploration, put aside the issue of sex
discrimination, as this MicroSort-using company does. They have a rule to
fend off that objection. You can only go there and use that sperm sorting
technique if you already have kids and you want to use it for family
balancing. They won't let you use it to stock up on boys or on girls, and
you can't even use it for your first child. So they've found a very clever
way to put the sex-discrimination argument, the sex-skewing argument to
rest.
That poses the question very clearly. Insofar as there is
something troubling about this, beyond safety, beyond fairness, what is
it? It seems to me something morally troubling does persist in each of
these cases. And what is it?
Think back to the case of genetically
enhanced athletes. Some people say what's wrong there it's a moral wrong
beyond fairness is the genetically enhanced athletes running
three-minute miles or hitting 700-foot home runs routinely. There is
something about enhancement that undermines effort, the nobility of
effort, the sober, hard-forged virtues that attend really working and
striving and training so that your accomplishments, be they athletic or
otherwise, are really your doing. It's one thing to hit 70 home runs as
the result of discipline, training and effort, this argument goes, and
something else, something less, to hit them with the help of steroids or
genetically enhanced muscles.
There is something in this idea, but
I would argue the problem with enhancement is not that it erodes effort
and undermines human agency. In fact, it's something closer to the
opposite. The deeper danger is that genetic enhancement and bioengineering
represent a kind of hyper-agency, a kind of Promethean aspiration to
remake nature, including human nature, to serve our purposes and to
satisfy our desires. The problem is not the drift to mechanism, where we
imagine even robotic athletes. The problem is the drive to mastery. What
the drive to mastery misses and may even destroy is an appreciation of the
gifted character of human powers and achievements.
To acknowledge
the giftedness of life is to recognize that our talents and powers are not
wholly our own doing, despite the efforts we expend to develop and to
exercise them. Appreciating the gifted quality of life constrains the
Promethean and conduces to a certain humility. This sense of giftedness is
in part a religious sensibility, but its resonance reaches beyond
religion, and there are ways of understanding this idea, this ethic, that
don't depend on religious notions.
To go back to the athletic
example, consider two types of athletic achievement. There are players
like Pete Rose who aren't blessed with great natural gifts but who manage,
somehow, through effort and grit and determination and striving, to excel
in their sport. But we also admire players like Joe DiMaggio, whose
excellence consists in the grace and effortlessness with which they
display their natural gifts. Now do a thought experiment. Suppose we
learned that both players took performance-enhancing drugs. Whose turn to
drugs would we find more deeply disillusioning? Which aspect of the
athletic ideal, effort or gift, would be more deeply offended? Some might
say effort. The problem with the drug is that it's a short cut. It's a way
to win without the effort and without the striving. But effort and
striving are not the point of sports. Excellence is. And excellence
consists, at least partly, in the display of natural talents and gifts
that are no doing of the athlete who possesses them.
This is an
uncomfortable fact for democratic societies because we want to believe
that in life and in sports success is something we earn, not something we
inherit. And so natural gifts and the admiration they inspire embarrass
the meritocratic faith; they cast doubt on the conviction that praise and
rewards flow from effort alone.
And so in the face of this
embarrassment we inflate the moral significance of effort and striving and
we depreciate giftedness. We can see this, for example, in the television
coverage of the Olympics, where they focus less on the feats the athletes
perform than on those heart-rending stories of the hardships they've
overcome, the obstacles they've surmounted, the struggles they've waged to
triumph over an injury or political turmoil in their native land. That's
all about the valorization of effort over giftedness, and it reflects our
uneasiness in a democratic, meritocratic society with that ethic.
But effort isn't everything. No one believes that a mediocre
basketball player who works very hard, even harder than Michael Jordan,
deserves greater acclaim or a bigger contract. And so the real problem
with genetically altered athletes is that they corrupt athletic
competition as a human activity that honors the cultivation and display of
natural talents. From this standpoint, enhancement can be seen as the
ultimate expression of the ethic of effort and willfulness, a kind of
high-tech striving. If this is what's at stake, crowding out the ethic of
giftedness in favor of a kind of overbearing, strenuous striving, it isn't
only genetic enhancement that raises these objections.
In the
National Football League over the past 30 years there has been a dramatic
increase in the average size of players, especially linebackers. In 1972
in the Super Bowl, the average weight of an offensive lineman was anyone
care to hazard a guess? 248 pounds already pretty big. That was in
1972. Today the average Super Bowl lineman weighs 304 pounds. And a year
ago the Dallas Cowboys boasted the NFL's first 400-pound player. Now, this
isn't all accounted for by steroid use, because the NFL banned steroids in
the 1990s. What produced these gargantuan athletes was a very low-tech
thing: huge amounts of food. (Laughter.) A reporter for The New York Times
looked into this and said, "As the pressure increases to add pounds, the
science of size comes down to a cocktail of unregulated supplements and a
bag of cheeseburgers."
So the phenomenon I'm describing is not
solely a question of high-tech. There is nothing high-tech about a
mountain of Big Macs. And yet encouraging athletes to use mega-calorie
diets to turn themselves into 400-pound human shields and battering rams
is as ethically questionable is questionable in the same way as
encouraging them to bulk up through the use of steroids or human growth
hormone or genetic alterations. Whatever the means to push for super-size
players is degrading to the game and to the dignity of those who transform
their bodies to meet its demands.
So we have the ethic of
giftedness, which is under siege in sports. It persists, though it's also
under siege in the practice of parenting. To appreciate children as gifts
is to accept them as they come, not as objects of our design or products
of our will or instruments of our ambition. And this goes to the issue of
sex selection, but not only sex selection, also, in principle, down the
road, the use of genetic technologies to select other traits of children,
whether height, eye color, hair color, or ultimately, though not anytime
soon, intelligence, athletic prowess, musical ability and the like.
So here, too, is a pressure on the ethic of giftedness. We choose
our friends and spouses at least partly on the basis of qualities that we
find attractive, but we do not choose our children. Their qualities are
unpredictable, and even the most conscientious parents can't be held
wholly responsible for the kind of child they have. That's why parenthood,
more than other human relationships, teaches what my friend, theologian
and bioethicist William May calls "an openness to the unbidden."
This helps us see that the deepest moral objection to enhancement
or to the pursuit of designer children lies not in the perfection that it
seeks, but in the human disposition that it expresses and promotes. The
problem is not that parents usurp the autonomy of the child whose sex they
choose or whose traits they design, because the child wouldn't otherwise
choose her genetic traits for herself. Autonomy is not what's at issue.
The problem lies in the hubris of the designing parents in their drive to
master the mystery of birth. Even if this disposition doesn't make parents
tyrants to their children, still it disfigures the relation of parent and
child and deprives the parent of the humility and of the enlarged human
sympathies that an openness to the unbidden can cultivate.
Now,
it's tricky, this ethic of giftedness, because it doesn't mean that it's
not our place to try to mold or cultivate or to improve our children. We
admire parents who seek the best for their children, who spare no effort
to help them achieve happiness and success. Some parents do this by
sending their kids to expensive schools, hiring private tutors, packing
them off to tennis camp, giving them piano lessons, ballet lessons,
swimming lessons, SAT prep courses and so on. We all know about that,
don't we? And so here's the question: If it's permissible for parents to
help their children in these ways, why isn't it equally permissible and
admirable for parents to use whatever genetic technologies are around,
provided they're safe, to enhance their child's intelligence or musical
ability insofar as that became possible?
The defenders of
enhancement point out that analogy, and they're right to this extent:
Improving children through genetic engineering is similar in spirit to the
heavily managed, high-pressure childrearing practices that have become
common these days. But this similarity doesn't vindicate genetic
enhancement. To the contrary, it highlights a problem with the trend
toward hyper-parenting. And we're familiar with this trend, even apart
from the high-tech expressions of it.
Consider sports-crazed
parents bent on making champions of their children. Never mind the
sidelines of the weekend soccer games that so many of us populate, and the
crazed parents alongside us not us, but they're the crazed ones.
(Laughter.) Richard Williams, the father of Venus and Serena Williams, the
great tennis champions, reportedly planned the tennis careers of his
daughters before they were born. Or Earl Woods, the father of Tiger Woods,
handed a golf club to the young Tiger while he was still in the playpen.
But it's not only parents bent on making champions of their children in
sports. More pervasive still is the frenzied drive by parents to mold and
manage their children's academic careers. When I was in high school I
didn't know anyone who went and took a SAT prep course. Now just about
everybody seems to do that. It's a $2.5 billion industry now.
And
SAT prep courses aren't the only way that the anxious affluent polish and
package their college-bound progeny. After all, hyper-parenting is
strenuous and time consuming, so some parents subcontract the job to
private counselors and consultants. There is a firm in Manhattan it
would have to be in Manhattan (laughter) called IvyWise. They offer a
two-year platinum package of college admissions help for how much do you
suppose? $32,995. Over 10 percent of today's college freshman have used
paid counselors of one kind or another, up from 1 percent in 1990. And
it's not only to get kids into college. IvyWise has a service for kids
that caters to parents eager to win spots for their children in the
coveted private elementary schools in New York. And we heard a year or two
ago about this guy, Jack Grubman, a Wall Street stock analyst, who
upgraded his rating, allegedly, of AT&T stock to curry favor with his
boss who was helping get his twin two-year-olds admitted to a prestigious
nursery school.
We've strayed from the issue of high tech, and
even genetic enhancement, but the ethic at stake, the drive for designer
children to mold and manage, is the same, and it's objectionable. It's
animated by the same kind of ethic and impulse of mastery and control, and
it's objectionable, it seems to me, on the same grounds. Mr. Grubman's
willingness to move heaven and earth, and even the market, to get his
two-year-olds into a fancy nursery school is a sign of the times. It tells
of mounting pressures in American life that are changing the expectations
parents have for their children, and increasing the demands placed on
children to perform.
And so it's no wonder that as the pressure
for performance increases, so does the need to help distractible children
concentrate on the task at hand. Enter Ritalin. Ritalin prescriptions for
children and adolescents have tripled over the past decade, but not all
users suffer from ADHD. It's also possible to use Ritalin to enhance one's
performance on the SAT or on college exams.
So those who argue
that bioengineering is similar in spirit to other ways that ambitious
parents shape and mold their children have a point, but this doesn't give
us a reason to embrace the genetic manipulation of children. Instead it
gives us reason to question the low-tech, high-pressure childrearing
practices that we increasingly accept. The hyper-parenting, familiar in
our time, represents an anxious excess of mastery and dominion that misses
the sense of life as gift, and this draws it disturbingly close to
eugenics, which is what gets at the fundamental moral stakes.
The
shadow of eugenics hangs over today's debates about genetic engineering
and enhancement. Critics say what we're witnessing with enhancement is
nothing more than privatized or free-market eugenics. Defenders of
enhancement say, No, no, it's not eugenics, provided there is no state
imposition; provided there is no coercion. Historic eugenics involved
forced sterilization, coerced by the state, and ultimately, with the
Nazis, genocide. The Nazis gave eugenics a bad name, but the question
remains now, what was wrong with eugenics? Was it just the coercion and
the state imposition, or is something wrong with eugenics even if there is
no state imposition, even if there is no coercion? That's another way of
framing the question about genetic enhancement.
James Watson, who
with Francis Crick discovered the structure of DNA, has argued that there
is nothing wrong with genetic engineering and enhancement, provided they
are freely chosen, not state-imposed. A couple of years ago, he stirred up
a controversy by saying that if a gene for homosexuality were discovered,
a pregnant woman who didn't want a homosexual child should be free to
abort a fetus that carried it. When his remark provoked an uproar, Watson
replied, he wasn't singling out gays but asserting a principle, namely
that women should be free to abort fetuses for any reason of genetic
preference, whether the child would be born dyslexic or lacking musical
talent or too short to play basketball.
The furor over Watson's
remark poses starkly this question about free market eugenics. Even for
those who don't subscribe to the pro-life position, Watson's scenario
raises a hard question. If it's morally troubling to contemplate abortion
to avoid a gay child or a dyslexic one, doesn't this suggest that there is
something wrong with acting on eugenic preferences, even where no
state-imposed coercion is involved?
Take a tamer example. There
are ads that run in campus newspapers, including those on my campus,
looking for egg donors. A few years ago a fertility clinic ran an ad in
some Ivy League college newspaper seeking an egg from a woman who met
certain qualifications: at least 5'10" tall, athletic, without major
medical problems, and with a combined SAT of 1400 or above. And in
exchange for an egg from this donor, they were willing to pay the ad
offered do you remember how much? $50,000 for that designer egg.
What about that? How does that strike you? If it bothers you
somehow, doesn't it suggest, as with Watson's scenario now here there's
no coercion, there's no state imposition isn't it the eugenic character
of the ad, of the practice that's troubling? The problem, then, with
eugenic and genetic engineering is that both represent the one-sided
triumph of willfulness over giftedness, of dominion and mastery over
reverence and restraint.
Now why should we worry if the ethic of
mastery and dominion and control crowds out the ethic of giftedness? We
should worry because if the genetic revolution erodes our appreciation for
the gifted character of power human powers and achievements it would
transform at least two key features of our moral landscape, and they're
connected. One is humility, and one is solidarity.
In a social
world that prizes mastery and control, like ours, parenthood is a school
for humility. That we care deeply about our children and yet can't choose
the kind we want teaches parents to be open to the unbidden. Such openness
is a disposition worth affirming, not only within families, but in the
wider world as well, because it invites us to abide the unexpected, to
live with dissonance, to rein in the impulse to control. A world in which
parents became accustomed to selecting the sex and genetic traits of their
children would be a world inhospitable to the unbidden; it would be a
gated community writ large.
But this aspect of humility is
connected to the moral basis of social solidarity. Why, after all, do the
successful owe anything to the least advantaged members of society? The
best answer to that question leans heavily on the notion of giftedness. It
goes like this: The natural talents that enable some of us to flourish and
get ahead, make a lot of money those talents aren't wholly our own
doing, but rather in large part our good fortune. If our genetic
endowments are gifts rather than achievements for which we can claim
credit, then it's a mistake and a conceit to assume that we are entitled
to the full measure of the bounty our talents reap in a market society.
Therefore, we have an obligation to share our bounty with those who,
through no fault of their own, lack comparable gifts.
So here's
the connection between solidarity and giftedness. Those who retain a
lively sense of the contingency of their gift, those who realize that we
aren't wholly responsible for our success, are more likely to take a more
generous stance toward those who lack the talents the market happens to
prize. Giftedness, in other words, saves a meritocratic society from
sliding into the smug assumption that the rich are rich because they are
more deserving than the poor.
But what happens when genetic
engineering enables us to override the results of the natural lottery, to
replace chance with choice? The gifted character of human powers and
achievements would recede and with it, perhaps, our capacity to see
ourselves as sharing a common fate. The successful, thinking themselves
wholly self-made men and women, would become even more likely than now to
view themselves as self-sufficient and, hence, wholly responsible for
their success.
Those at the bottom of society would no longer be
viewed as disadvantaged and so worthy of a measure of compensation, but
simply as unfit and so worthy of eugenic repair. The meritocracy, less
chastened by chance, would become harder, less forgiving. So here's how
solidarity is connected to, draws upon, requires a certain ethic of
giftedness and a certain sense of the chance, an appreciation of the
chanced nature of our lot.
But against it is arrayed a powerful
project of mastery, control and self-making. There is something appealing,
even intoxicating about a vision of human freedom unfettered by the given.
It may even be the case that the allure of that vision played a part in
summoning the genomic age into being. It's often assumed that the powers
of enhancement we now possess arose as an inadvertent byproduct of
biomedical progress. The genetic revolution came, so to speak, to cure
disease and then stayed to tempt us with the prospect of enhancing our
performance, designing our children and perfecting our nature.
But
that may have the story backwards. It's more plausible to view genetic
engineering as the ultimate expression of the ethic I've been describing,
of the resolve to see ourselves astride the world, the masters of our
nature. What I've tried to suggest is that that premise of mastery is
flawed. It threatens to banish our appreciation of life as a gift and to
leave us with nothing outside our own will, our own resources, our own
effort to affirm or behold.
Thanks very much.
(Applause.)
MR. DIONNE: Thank you very much.
While Dr. Silver sets up,
when you talked about the search for that egg-based on SAT scores, I
thought you had stumbled across a joint venture between IvyWise and
MicroSort (laughter). It was extraordinary.
Sir, welcome. Thank
you so much for being with us.
LEE M. SILVER: I want to
thank the organizers of this conference for giving me the opportunity to
respond to Professor Sandel's analysis of the rights and wrongs of parents
choosing which genes their children receive and the modification of nature
in general.
I have to confess I have no background in bioethics. I
was trained as a physicist, and I did molecular biology most of my life,
and I don't pretend to have any answers to the hard questions. I see my
role as a provocateur to raise the questions even though I can't answer
them. And I do this because I enjoy it, but also because most scientists
try their hardest not to provoke. Jim Watson and Francis Crick are notable
exceptions because they became historical figures in their own time, and
they didn't have to worry about anything. Jim Watson discovered the double
helix at the age of 25.
I don't like where all of this competition
leads. I have a daughter in 11th grade, and I was forced to put her into a
$1000 SAT prep course because most other parents were advantaging their
children in the same way. I don't like the fact that 50 percent of
Princeton University undergraduates seek psychological counseling at some
point during their four years on campus. But I don't think it's just the
parents who are to blame. It's also our modern American society, where
success is based ever more on achievement and even less on who your father
is, although our president is a glaring exception to that rule. (Scattered
laughter.) And so we end up with what biologists call the red queen
effect, which biologists have known about for a long time. It's based on
the Lewis Carroll character, who has to keep running just to stay in
place.
In evolutionary biology, it's impossible to escape the red
queen. Darwin was the one who said that every species is going to go
extinct because some individuals within that species would out compete
other individuals in that species with new genes, and so if we look just
back at our recent evolutionary past, homo erectus went extinct, homo
Neanderthal went extinct, homo habilis went extinct. All those species
were in our past. They didn't survive; they all went extinct. I homo
sapien is different, but we'll get to that later on.
So I agree
with Professor Sandel that this is a very worrisome trend. I don't like
it, but it's not clear to me how we can stop it in a democratic society. I
also agree with him that to understand the ethics of enhancement of any
kind, we must ask questions about the moral status of nature and about the
proper stance of human beings toward the given world. And I think that
secular academics often engage this debate with one hand tied behind their
back because they ignore an area which is very important to most people,
which Professor Sandel has not ignored, actually. As he explains, the
political leanings of a person do not necessarily provide insight into
that person's answers to moral questions about the modification of nature.
Some on both the right and the left of the political spectrum are opposed
to human tampering with genes, and Professor Sandel presents a carefully
reasoned and sincere liberal argument against gene control. But even
further to the left are people who are more vociferous in their opposition
to all forms of plant, animal and human biotechnology.
In
contrast, some thoughtful people, both conservatives and liberals, fail to
see a problem with genetic enhancement as long as it doesn't restrict the
child's autonomy. Indeed the well-known, left-wing, Harvard
scientist-authors Richard Lewontin and Stephen Jay Gould couldn't even
figure out why there was such a big fuss about reproductive cloning. They
didn't see it raising any new ethical issues. That's contrary to what
almost everybody else in the country believes. I'm not going to talk about
cloning, but I think it shows that there's a fundamental distinction
between the way that people view life. It's not politics. In my opinion,
the answer is based fundamentally on different conceptualizations of
spirituality.
Now I had a religious upbringing, and I didn't
question it when I was being brought up. But then I became an adult and a
molecular biologist, and people didn't talk about religion any more in
molecular biology, or actually anywhere else I talked to secular
academics. And I remember bringing up this in discussion with my molecular
biology colleagues at Princeton, talking about spiritual beliefs at a
faculty lunch, and Leon Rosenberg, who is a esteemed colleague of mine,
said, quote, "No educated person believes in souls." I went home that
evening, and I remember having dinner with my father-in-law, who is a very
educated person, and he said, quote, "No educated person denies the
existence of souls." So here was clearly a contradiction. What was the
truth?
Spiritual beliefs, whether admitted or not, are nearly
universal, but the details of such beliefs can vary tremendously from
culture to culture, from person to person, even within the same religious
tradition. I traveled across Asia and North Africa and Europe and asked
people what they thought about the soul.
Westerners especially
don't like to use that word, and so they use euphemisms for the soul. Most
non-Westerners think the soul is a wispy, spatially localized material
substance that leaves the body and goes somewhere else after death, but
it's not just non-Westerners. In 1907, The New York Times headlined an
article, quote, "Soul Has Weight, Physician Thinks." Now, forget about the
use of the English language there, it was based on an experiment published
in a journal called American Medicine, which doesn't exist anymore, and he
weighed people. He put people on a giant balance while they were dying of
tuberculosis and weighed them and claimed in his results that they lost 21
grams at the moment of death. That's not an urban legend; that's a real
experiment that was published in a medical journal.
Now,
Descartes, who lived before then, understood the scientific implausibility
of a material substance that had a mind of its own which could leave the
body, so Descartes said the soul is not a material substance, it's a
different kind of substance a spiritual substance without location or
mass. But the material soul and Cartesian souls were both immortal. They
survived the death of the body.
The third category of soul, which
originated with Aristotle, is not immortal. In modern language this type
of soul is an emergent property of the human body, or just the human mind.
It can't possibly exist in isolation from the body, so when the body dies,
it dies.
And the fourth category of soul is what Francis Crick
made famous when he said you are nothing but a pack of neurons in his book
Soul as a Metaphor. The soul is a metaphor for whatever you want it to be.
These are very, very different views of the soul.
At the
invitation of the Council of Catholic Bishops Committee on Science and
Human Values, I had the opportunity last fall to speak with a group of
American bishops at an informal lunch, and I asked them to explain the
Catholic notion of soul to me. I was surprised when they disagreed with
each other. Some thought the human soul survived as an immaterial spirit,
and some thought it didn't that it would only come back when the body
was resurrected. That the leaders of a religious culture disagreed on this
fundamental issue suggests to me that they didn't talk about it with each
other very much.
In a poll I conducted at Princeton University, 66
percent of Princeton University students said they believed in a human
soul of some kind; 53 percent believe specifically in immaterial soul; 27
percent had no idea what they thought. And many of the students were very
disturbed that I actually forced them to consider the answer to this
question.
I think this is a product of our scientific culture.
Pre-scientific people are not confused. When I was in Bali watching a
cremation ceremony where the soul is supposed to go up in the smoke to
heaven, people were happy. They didn't fear death. They weren't upset.
They were all very happy that this old woman's soul was going up to
heaven. In the Mayan culture in Central America that I visited, they bury
the dead and the soul seeps out into the ground. It has to fight off the
underworld before it gets into heaven.
Science causes anxiety and
confusion in moral beliefs. It's science starting from the Enlightenment
period that suggested that God is not needed to explain the revolutions of
the planets around the sun; and in the 20th century, biochemists have not
needed God to explain the workings of living cells. Professor Sandel
worries about what he calls the deeper danger of Promethean aspiration to
remake nature, including human nature, and satisfy our desires. But every
human civilization came into existence only when people acquired a
primitive understanding of heredity, which allowed them to remake nature.
The Mayans in Central America took a weed and turned it into corn. Asians
took wild oxen and turned them into docile milk factories we call cows.
Most people think that cows and corn were here at the origin as a gift,
but in fact they are human inventions.
Today, 36 percent of the
land mass of the earth is dedicated to agriculture, and the UN thinks it
will be 50 percent by the year 2050. In most populated areas of the world
there is nothing left of the nature that existed before humankind invaded.
So I'm not happy about that either, but if you look at the alternative, we
have six billion people on Earth. If we didn't use a significant amount of
land mass, there'd be massive starvation, so that's the alternative.
It's fascinating to me that if you look at American spiritual
beliefs, European spiritual beliefs, they give you some insight into what
kinds of biotechnology are disliked. In America there's a very strong
traditional Judeo-Christian ethic, and in Judeo-Christian ethic only human
beings get souls, not animals and plants, and that has a very strong
impact on our political system, I believe. So we don't worry too much
about genetically modified crops because crops were given to us to benefit
humankind.
In Europe, many of left-leaning European intellectuals
have a different version of spirituality, which encompasses all of Mother
Nature, and in that kind of spirituality, they categorically reject
genetically modified foods. Liberal society has functioned and tried very,
very hard to make the claim that genes really don't matter. My children
were taught in public schools that they could accomplish anything their
hearts desire. Brilliant leaders of the Human Genome Project like Eric
Lander and Craig Venter argue that genetic analysis shows that we're all
99.9 percent identical to each other, which is true, which means that
there are three million genetic differences between individuals, so it's a
question of how you look at that.
As Professor Sandel knows, and
we all know today, we can't hide the fact that there are differences in
genetic distribution. The human species is not monolithic. Each child is
born with different degrees of genetic advantage and disadvantage at the
starting points along thousands and thousands of curves. As the child
grows up, they can push up and down from the starting points, I believe,
but the genetic mythology has always been, in liberal society that anybody
can do anything they want. That's simply not true. In fact, most people
especially today have no chance of being a professional athlete or an
Olympic contender or a violinist in the Boston Symphony Orchestra. Today
you can't compensate just with strong work. You have to be born way, way,
way out along the curve on your profession. And I suspect even Pete Rose
was not average. I would say that he was probably in the 95th percentile
perhaps and that's and then his effort allowed him, but probably
wouldn't be able to succeed today because you have to be in the 99.99
percentile.
And I just want to show you a picture in the middle of
Professor Sandel's article, which is very ironic. This is a picture from
The Atlantic. It's an advertisement using Lance Armstrong, who is winner
of the Tour de France four times in a row. Lance Armstrong is not a normal
human being. When I looked up on the web "superhuman" next to "Lance
Armstrong," I got 570 hits. Everybody thinks he's superhuman. He has
massive lungs and his heart is 30 percent larger than average. He's in the
99.99 percentile and that's one of the reasons he's always tested clean on
drug tests. The reason that he's winning these races, besides the fact
that he has put in a lot of hard effort, is the fact that he is
genetically gifted.
Now most people in Western societies like
people like Lance Armstrong, but they're troubled when you talk about
parents being able to give their children exactly the same kind of gene
that some other children get naturally. So I'm not talking about running
the mile in two minutes; I'm talking about parents who are saying to
themselves, Well, my neighbor's kids have genes which allow their children
to compete athletically or in some other way; why can't I just give my
children the same genes? What is wrong with that? If they're given
naturally to him, why can't I give them to myself?
In the United
States we have this notion, which was demonstrated in Harper's Magazine
index there was a question people were asked: Who should decide what
genes a child gets? And the four possible answers were: parents, doctor,
no one, or God. God came in first place with 70 percent; no one came in
second place with 16 percent; and the parents came in third place with 11
percent. And then in the very same survey same poll, same population
they asked people: If you could give your child enhanced genes that would
increase his resistance to disease, would you do it? Then 75 percent said
yes. So, you know, in the abstract they don't want to think about playing
with genes, but then you give them a specific example of how they can
advantage their own child and they hadn't thought about that. They'd like
to be able to take advantage of that.
The problem is the vision of
nature and the notion that nature is spiritual, I think, underlies the
feeling that we shouldn't tamper with it that nature gives us gifts is
the word Professor Sandel uses. Molecular biologists and other biologists
in related fields don't see nature in the same way, and I think that is
the division between the way people think categorically about what the
opponents call genetic tampering. Molecular biologists and anybody who has
had an evolutionary biology course knows that nature, if you want to be
metaphorical, is mean and nasty; that everything is trying to kill
everything else; that a turtle lays 1,000 eggs, 1,000 little turtles hatch
and 999 of them are going to die before they make it back into the water.
In the book he wrote just before he died, Stephen Jay Gould and
he was no friend of the right wing wrote, "I would advance the strong
claim that Darwin's theory of natural selection is in essence Adam Smith's
economics transferred to nature." He only was able to write this right
before he died because it went against his political beliefs.
So
the point I think I'd like to make is that we ignore something that is an
inherent part of most people's personalities, which is some kind of
spiritual belief; and spiritual beliefs are not monolithic. They can be
all over the place, but scientists especially want to ignore the
spirituality. Scientists are the least spiritual, molecular biologists are
the least spiritual of all groups of people that I've ever encountered.
They want to ignore the spirituality. They want to not provoke people.
They want to try to explain it in secular terms. The problem I have is
that I don't see a secular reason to stop parents from giving a child a
gene that other parents give their children naturally, not in a society
where we know that the playing field is not fair to begin with. If a
playing field was fair, I think it would be different, and I think that's
why the mythology of "everybody starts at the same place," of "the playing
field is level," that liberal mythology is put upon us to try to convince
people that anybody can get anywhere they want. It's not true we now know,
and that causes a severe problem for which I have no answer.
Thank
you very much. (Applause.)
MR. DIONNE: Mike wants to reply later
in the course of answering questions.
I want to ask one myself,
but I'd like to invite William May and Janet Rowley to be thinking if you
would like to join in at some point in this discussion, if you wouldn't
mind leading off after I ask a question.
By the way, there is an
explanation for that Harper's poll finding, which is 90 percent of the
parents thought they were God, which is perfectly logical with the data.
Which actually gets to the point: I find myself very sympathetic,
as you know, Michael, with your argument. "There but for the grace of God
go I" is to me one of the most politically and socially constructive moral
sentiments there is, and so I'm sympathetic when you say, "And what the
drive to mastery misses and may even destroy is an appreciation of the
gifted character of human power and achievements." And you go on:
"Appreciating the gifted quality of life constrains the Promethean project
and conduces a certain humility."
Here's the problem or the
question I have: Why is this objection to this particular technology any
different than objections to earlier forms of technology? Did not the fact
that some of us live longer than others also produce a sense of the gifted
character of life? Could that not be used at any point against
interventions by medical science? Christian Scientists, for example,
believe profoundly in the very sense of humility which you extol and which
I also admire. They would carry it farther down the line to saying that
many of the heroic interventions that we engage in are Promethean and
arrogant. How do you draw that line and where does a hard line need to be
drawn?
MR. SANDEL: Right. Yeah. Really a good and difficult
question, and it enables me to say that what I don't want to do is
enshrine as a general principle that human beings must not tamper with
nature. I think that would be folly and it would be at odds with a great
many wondrous and beneficial interventions in nature, and transformations
of nature that human beings have undertaken throughout human history. And
it would give rise to the very question you put. Well, what about surgery?
Does that mean we can't have surgery or anesthesia or any of the very
obvious cases, to say nothing of domestic cattle or hybrid corn and so on.
So my brief is not for enshrining nature as inviolable and not
open to human intervention or manipulation, so that in a way makes my task
more difficult then. How is it possible to work out an ethic of giftedness
that carries with it certain restraints, but that doesn't just say
whatever's given by nature is to be inviolable? And the kind of first step
I would try to offer to answer that question is that in addition to the
side of nature as a given we have to add, in any of these cases that we're
deliberating or wrestling with, some account a persuasive account of
the human goods that are at stake in this or that practice.
So
there is an account of the human good that I think has to govern any ethic
of giftedness mastery, restraint, intervention; not just the fact that
something is given by nature. So in the case of designer children, the
argument would have to be not just that it's wrong to tamper with your
kids. You should just let them come as they sprang from nature. That I
wouldn't say, because then can you give your kid a vaccination? No, not on
that account. Or a surgery or any kind of medical intervention? No.
By arguing from a certain account of the human goods at stake in
the case of designer children, I would have to be able to show that
getting in the habit of specifying the genetic traits let's say the
height, hair color, eye color, as they did in that movie Gattica. I don't
did you see Gattica? It's a great illustration of this where it's a
science fiction movie where they get in the habit of specifying not just
to prevent genetic diseases, but also to choose, as consumers would
choose, height, hair color, and various physical talents and attributes.
My argument would have to be that a society like that, where that kind of
designer child rearing became routine, would transform the relation
between parents and children in a way that would undermine important goods
that attach to the feature of childrearing now that depends importantly on
not commodifying or objectifying kids not viewing them as instruments of
our ambition, and when we run afoul of that, even in low-tech ways, we
feel guilty about it or can be recalled from it or are aware that were
going too far.
So you're absolutely right. It's not just the idea
of nature or the given. This ethic of giftedness has to make its case
practice by practice in relation to a certain count of the human goods
that are present in a practice that would be undermined by this kind of
intervention.
MR. DIONNE: Let me just follow up if I could. If I
read you right, you would not be opposed to, as it were, fixing genes that
might cause cancer.
MR. SANDEL: Right.
MR. DIONNE: Now,
let's say we know that obesity can cause premature death, so is there a
problem with fixing genes for obesity? Let us say there is significant
scientific evidence that in fact shows we could go either way, but let's
say that tall people actually have significantly longer lives and are
less given to disease than shorter people. How does one go from
MR. SILVER: And they make more money.
MR. DIONNE: Yeah,
that, too, but let's say I'm trying to keep it to the issue of fixing
for health.
MR. SANDEL: Right.
MR. DIONNE: As you go along
that continuum, where do you stop? How do you know when to stop?
MR. SANDEL: Right. Those are getting into some of the close cases:
obesity and height. And there it would depend on what the meaning of the
practice were of enhancing the height, which was why we would need to
know, are parents really starting now to enhance height because there is
this health reason? It's like obesity. If you're too short, you're it's
as if you're at-risk, which probably isn't true. I don't know. But
obesity, yes, then it's getting close, but if it really is for a genuine
health reason. But height, for just the reason that Professor Silver just
suggested well, it's also to be taller is more prestigious, carries
certain social advantages, gives you a higher income. Then it's shading
into non-medical reasons and insofar as those reasons come to predominate
the practice of height enhancement, to that extent I would say no.
MR. DIONNE: I just want to press you one last time on this.
MR. SANDEL: Yeah.
MR. DIONNE: The scientific data on the
relationship between obesity and health problems is quite substantial. Let
us say that there were not as overwhelmingly convincing evidence, but a
rather substantial set of correlations between height and health. And let
us say that my secret desire is to have my kid be a basketball player, but
I would give the public reason based on some significant data that I would
present you, and you would be the judge and say, Look, this is about
health, not about playing basketball. It strikes me that even though I am
very sympathetic to the distinction you want to make, I am wondering how
we as a society could get to the point of successfully making that
distinction.
MR. SANDEL: Well, there's no easy way of making that
distinction, but I would just point out that that difficulty isn't
distinctive to this issue of genetic enhancement. It's the same kind of
difficulty we confront all the time when, for example, we're trying to
decide whether a certain kind of proposed law or policy that might have
some benefit for religious practice is motivated by the desire to
strengthen some religious practices over others or whether it's really
justified because there are correlations that show that when these various
religious institutions are supported there are other good effects on
society.
All the time we have to try to sort out the actual
reasons that are given publicly from the real motivations that are
operating socially and wrestle with that. So I agree that's a difficulty,
but I don't think it's one that's distinctive to this case. I think it's
familiar in all kinds of discriminations that we make where questions of
moral judgment or ethical principle arise in politics. Even take tax cuts.
Is someone really offering a tax cut just to cater to the base, selfish
preferences of the people to whom he's promising it, or does he really
believe and is there evidence to support that it will increase economic
growth? We have this debate all the time. How do we know the answer to
that? I could say, Well, it's difficult. We sort of know how to probe that
kind of question. I would say that the example you've given is a very good
one, but not different fundamentally from what we do all the time.
MR. DIONNE: I will come back to that if I have a chance, but there
are too many good people in the audience not to call upon. Janet Rowley,
would you like to join us?
JANET ROWLEY: (Off mike.)
MR.
DIONNE: William May
WILLIAM MAY: I think Michael has offered an
answer to this form of one-sidedness where openness to the unbidden means
open to the cancer, this and that, and do nothing about it. Obviously he's
not suggesting a quietistic response to the human condition.
You
raise the question whether there's a secular way of acknowledging what I
would call the two sides to human existence, and I think E. B. White once
put it, in that oft quoted line, "Every morning when I wake up I'm torn
between the twin desire to reform the world and enjoy the world, and it
makes it hard to plan the day." There are two sides to our life. There are
two sides to science: beholding nature the inquiry for the truth but
also molding nature. There are two sides to parenting: molding the child
that's surely our responsibility, surely to fight disease and so forth
but there's a tendency in our society not simply as a meritarian
culture, but an immigrant culture to overlook simply the savoring. Auden
once said there's a terrific pressure in American life because so many
came over in order to justify a better future for their kids to expect
their kids to outstrip them and to resort to any and all means to ensure
this outstripping of the parents' more constricted life in Europe.
There are all sorts of pressures towards one of the two sides, and
I think that's what Michael's paper is about. Now, that doesn't mean we
can redo the American character, but one needs to learn how to lean
against the weaknesses in our color our character, our drives, and our
dispositions. There's a powerful drive to control.
What one has to
deal with I heard a psychiatrist once say the most difficult thing to
expose for people who are very controlling is that in their controlling
they're out of control, and one has to curb against that kind of
one-sidedness. But it seems to me the two-sided nature of human existence
is what Michael wanted to preserve. And admittedly once you admit there
are two sides to the life that we live, it's always difficult to make that
operational. That's why no matter how much elucidation to the complexity
of being human there is, every new generation has to face afresh these
difficulties of how you make operational a life that is admittedly, as E.
B. White said, very complex from the get go when you wake up in the
morning.
MR. DIONNE: Thank you. Did you have a response?
MR. SILVER: I'd like to respond to that. I see nature through a
biological lens, since that's what my training was in, and there are a lot
of instincts I believe that we have normal human beings have. We want to
see connections to our children, which is actually what I think will avoid
the radical abuses of the technology that you're talking about. I wouldn't
feel connected to a basketball son, for example. So people generally want
their children to be pretty much like them, just a little bit prettier and
a little bit smarter. Right? I wouldn't want a child to look totally
different from me. I treasure the fact that my children have something
from me, and so I don't think that we're going to have this kind of thing
where parents are going to run off and there's some ideal beauty, which of
course is different all over the world, and we're going to latch onto
that.
I think that is normal human nature, and I think the word
control may not be the right word, because again there's an instinct among
all mammals to provide for the survival and the success of their children
not just human beings, but other mammals as well. So I think parents can
be overcontrolling, but I think the basic instinct is because they want
their children to succeed because that's the way we're wired.
MR.
DIONNE: Michael, do you have a thought? Dr. Rowley
MS. ROWLEY:
Well, I'm going to take the refuge of scientists, which is to be more
concrete. I certainly appreciated the opening remarks of Dr. Silver
because I feel also that bioethics though I've been educated by my
colleagues on the Council now for more than two years, I still feel quite
uneasy in discussing many of those principles from the standpoint, say, of
ethics or philosophy. I'm going to make two comments.
One is that
I think that if you look at the reality of the situation, we're a very,
very long way from being able to put genes into embryos or into young
children and actually be able to control how those genes function to
change complex traits. Simple traits and single genetic diseases that
certainly may come sooner rather than later, but to really think about
this as a prospect in that sense, I think, is not realistic. And many of
the cultural problems that we've been talking about are just that.
They're, as you say, low-tech: eating too much, ways of gaining something
rather than from very sophisticated science.
The other remark I
want to make, and I will preface this by saying I have the utmost
admiration for Michael Sandel, but I do want to take exception to the end
of his talk, which is also similar to the end of the article in The
Atlantic Monthly, which is the unplanned vision of what we're doing with
genomics. He suggests that in fact the story is backwards and we can view
genetic engineering as the ultimate expression of our resolve to see
ourselves astride the world. Now, that assumes that science is monolithic.
That assumes that there is really a plan that back in the '30s and '40s
somebody knew what understanding DNA and manipulating DNA what it was
going to lead to. At least in my own view, nothing could be further from
the truth.
Science is chaotic. Science is haphazard and
discoveries are haphazard, and then people put them together. The
discovery that DNA carried our genetic information was made in the '40s.
Watson and Crick and the double helix was in the middle '50s. The
discovery that bacteria contain substances enzymes that cut DNA and
that using these enzymes from bacteria you actually could take DNA and cut
it into hundreds of millions of pieces and then identify the gene or the
DNA that you want and select it out of these hundreds of millions of
pieces And then finally that you could move DNA these little pieces of
DNA, put them in carriers, put them in other cells, and change those other
cells. This was strictly haphazard, and there was no sense that there was
a resolve to see ourselves astride the world.
MR. DIONNE: Thank
you. Mike, please.
MR. SANDEL: Well, I wouldn't dispute for a
moment Dr. Rowley's account of the haphazard unfolding of the genetic
revolution. I think it's a more difficult question to know just how the
newfound genetic knowledge fit with and reinforced currents in the public
culture and in the moral culture and that aspired to a certain kind of
project of masteries. So I would not suggest that there was some
conspiracy on the part of scientists to come up with this thing for the
sake of mastery. No. Scientists were haphazardly making discoveries that
then had applications of medicine in cures. Yes, that I wouldn't question.
But I am intrigued to notice and at least reflect on the strains in the
culture that give a kind of momentum to this, taken as a kind of cultural
motif.
And here is where I was struck: the linking of the two I
found in this Robert Sinsheimer article, which was written in the late
1960s. He was a molecular biologist at Cal-Tech. About 35 years ago he
glimpsed the way this might unfold, and he emphasized both the science and
the human self-understandings that were at stake here. And that interested
me a lot, and that was really what I was referring to by this suggestion
that there might be an interplay here between the science and a petty
human self-image.
Sinsheimer first described the benefits to
humankind, medical and otherwise, but then he talked very much in terms of
the human self-image. He said, "As we enlarge man's freedom, we diminish
his constraints and that which he must accept as given." So now he's
talking in almost cosmological terms. And he talks about Copernicus and
Darwin, who demoted man from his right glory at the focal point of the
universe, but the new biology would restore human beings to their place at
the center. And so he's going all the way back looking on the history of
science in relation to its impact on human self-understandings, and then
he concludes: "We can be the agent of transition to a whole new pitch of
evolution." This is a cosmic event. That's Sinsheimer. It was really
reacting to that prescient in a way and also evocative account of the link
between science and human meanings, and even for a certain picture of the
cosmos, that led me to offer that speculation.
MR. SILVER: One
point I wanted to make is that all of medicine in a sense is enhancement.
All of medicine is attacking the problems in nature and medicine's been
very good for people who have lived in wealthy countries like ours over
the last 100 years. We talked about this earlier, but I think it's very
difficult to draw the line between curing disease and enhancement. Would
it be enhancement to have a better than average protection against
disease? It depends on how you define enhancement.
But I wanted to
respond also to what Dr. Rowley said. Different scientists think different
ways. In 1970, Jacques Monod wrote a book called Chance and Necessity, and
it's a brilliant little book. In the book he predicted that genetic
engineering would always be impossible because DNA was too small to
manipulate. Three years later, of course, genetic engineering was
accomplished with bacteria, and in 1980 genetic engineering was
accomplished with mice, and now the tools in the laboratory that we can
use with mice we can switch one base at a time in the mouse genome, so,
technically, I would disagree.
If you put a huge amount of money
into it, you could figure out how to do genetic engineering with human
embryos. I don't think it's going to happen anytime soon because I don't
think there's enough there to engineer that we know about at this point in
time. I think you're right. We know some things about disease traits, but
certainly nothing about the other kinds of things that people might be
interested in: intelligence and things like that.
And the last
comment I just wanted to make is that it's useful to talk about these
things because, just like with Jacques Monod being fooled into thinking
something wasn't possible, scientists often overestimate what they can do
in the short term and they underestimate what they can do in the long
term. I think that's true.
MR. DIONNE: Very interesting.
I
have the gift today of being in a room with not just one but two of my
favorite philosophers, and I'd like to call on Bill Galston to join the
discussion if he would.
BILL GALSTON: Well, in addition to reading
Michael's recent article with great attention, I've also read the report
of the President's Council, of which Professor Sandel is a member. And as
I read that report, it articulates, without quite putting it this way,
except once, three kinds of reservations against the thesis that you're
advancing. And I'd just like to put them on the table very quickly to give
you an opportunity to respond.
The first reservation, which is
really up-front in the report, is and this just piggybacks on what Dr.
Silver said that the distinction between therapy and enhancement, on
which a portion of your article conceptually pivots, I believe, is very
hard to maintain once you look at it carefully.
The second
objection is that many of our judgments about when certain sorts of
enhancements are and are not acceptable are relative to the social context
within which the proposed enhancement will or will not occur. And the
President's Council gives the example of enhancing the ability of
soldiers, through the kinds of means we've been talking about this
afternoon, so that they can fight more effectively and suggests that we
think much better of that possibility than we do of enhancing the ability
of athletes, and so that the social context matters.
The third
objection is I think goes to the heart of the argument you're making a
critique of the notion of giftedness and an ethic of giftedness as an
adequate guide to our conduct. And the President's Council points out that
nature throws up for our inspection all sorts of things, some of which
appear quite desirable and some of which much less so. And so beyond the
givenness of the natural is a set of judgments about whether what is put
forward is good or not good, humanly speaking, and it is those judgments,
rather than an ethic of giftedness as such, that ultimately determine what
we should do, which I guess brings me full circle to a question that Dr.
Silver put on the table, which I'll put this way: Can something be a gift
if there's no giver?
MR. SILVER: That's exactly the question that
I was asking. In my mind, a gift is given by something or someone, and
when we talk about gifts it's usually in the language of God or some other
kind of spiritual entity that is giving us the gifts. I've never heard
molecular biologists use that language. I'm stereotyping molecular
biologists, but they really have a different perspective of the world that
people in the social sciences and humanities. So to my mind a gift has to
have a giver.
Professor Sandel said we must feel indebted for this
gift. Who are we feeling indebted towards? So I'm not denying the
importance of religious beliefs in the public arena; I'm just suggesting
that that is a kind of religious or spiritual belief and that you can't
derive that from secular precepts.
MR. DIONNE: Michael?
MR. SANDEL: Okay, well, a lot of interesting questions there, and
I want to come to this in a minute, but to take Bill's first three
questions and then to the big question that he dropped upon us here like a
bombshell.
It's difficult to distinguish between therapy and
enhancement. What's medical? What's non-medical? Does creating a genetic
predisposition to be immune from certain diseases is that medical or
non-medical? Therapy or enhancement? (Unintelligible) or vaccination a
genetic form of a vaccination? Would that be therapeutic or would that be
an enhancement? Well, I agree that it's borderline, but I would be
inclined to say that it's for the sake of health, and so I wouldn't find
it subject to the same kinds of objections that worry me.
Now, to
say that it's for the sake of health is to say that we do need to
investigate the purpose or the good to be advanced by the intervention and
the wooden distinction standing by itself between therapy and enhancement
can't give us that, so yes, I agree entirely. We have to enquire to the
purpose, the point, the end, the good that's being advanced.
As
between the soldiers and the athletes, I don't think it's obvious. The
soldiers are performing a great good. The athlete is a good, but arguably
a lesser one. Still, if the
MR. DIONNE: Say that to a Quaker
baseball fan. (Laughter.)
MR. SANDEL: If the genetic alteration of
the soldiers is not for the sake of health their health then I think
it would be subject to the same kinds of worries that I would have even if
my favorite Red Sox player were I mean, the cause can be great there,
too, if it were the last day of the playoff against the Yankees and if
only Pedro Martinez had a little more endurance or, if lacking the ability
to increase his endurance genetically there were a way of providing a
cognition enhancer for Grady Little, I would have been (laughter) I
would have been tempted.
MR. GALSTON: Be honest. If you could have
spliced a new gene into Bill Buckner, would you have? (Laughter.)
MR. SANDEL: Right, but I think the general point is that in all of
these cases what matters is not the distinction between therapy and
enhancement itself, but an enquiry into the purposes, to the goods, to the
ends for the sake of which the intervention is justified. And in that
and the argument does have to hang on that, but having said that, I don't
see that as conceding that the ethic of giftedness is not doing moral work
here because part of the account of the good that I would bring to bear
part of the account of the human good is one that sees as impoverished a
mode of life that is bent on a certain kind of freedom as mastery or
dominion, which is why I try to show how that self-image was implicated in
the project of enhancement. Giftedness is a way of beginning to work out
at some general level an account of the human good at least insofar as our
stance toward nature and our own nature is concerned; though I agree; that
general account by itself won't be enough to decide each of these cases.
Finally, doesn't a gift presuppose a giver? I'm not sure. I think
that's an open question. At least I wanted to pose that and to leave that
as an open question. It seems to me in trying to work out an ethic of
giftedness as an ethic of restraint on the kinds of human hubris that lead
us to hyper-parenting or to genetic engineering. I think it's possible to
give multiple accounts of the source of that ethic and the source of those
restraints, and the three leading sources are God, nature and chance. And
I agree that trying to pursue each of those three might lead us to
different accounts of what it is to try to honor an ethic of giftedness
and to generate some restraints on the project of mastery, but I wouldn't
want too quickly to decide the question. I don't think it's an easily
decidable question whether an ethic of giftedness that gives rise to a
certain restraint on human dominion over nature and our own nature does or
doesn't require religion.
I do take this project as a whole as a
way of trying to bring back into public discourse as a live issue that
question. And there's a resistance to bring that into public discourse
because we get very uneasy when theological or metaphysical kinds of
issues come into public discourse. So I definitely want to lean against
that resistance in our culture, but I don't want to do it in a way that
just presupposes an answer to the question you posed, in part because I'm
not sure of the answer. I want to open that up at least for public
argument and debate.
MR DIONNE: Doesn't Bill's question does
there have to be a giver? help explain why those who are religious, who
do believe in God in some way, are far more likely to resist mastery, to
endorse humility, then? And that for people who do not believe in God that
is a much more difficult argument to make to them the one you're making?
MR. SANDEL: It's a good question, and I'm not sure because there
are some religious traditions and the Puritan tradition in the founding
of the American character could be an example that laid very great
emphasis on human initiative and the human vocation to transform the
world. That's a powerful part of the American character in a certain idea
of the American idea of freedom and mastery. And then there are other very
powerful religious sources that emphasize humility, restraint, the
restriction against not wanting to play God.
So I think there are
religious sources for both ethics and I also think maybe this is less
clear that there are ways of tapping into secular modes of reflection on
both sides, or at least I'm trying to invite even those who don't think of
themselves as religious or coming to a notion of giftedness through a
faith tradition, trying to invite secular people who have certain
intuitions that a way of making sense of those intuitions is via this idea
of giftedness.
Put aside genetic engineering. Think of debates
around environmental politics about the status of nature and whether the
reason for environmentalism is to keep the air clean for our children and
to avoid suffocating and so on greenhouse gas's terrible welfare
effects, or is there also something about a certain way of expressing our
stance towards nature that is important in its own right? I want to point
to features of our moral intuitions and even public debate that already
implicate even secular people in something like this idea. That's why I
don't want to decide too quickly or in a too hard and fast way how much of
this is religious and how much of this is secular. I want to blur that. I
want to kind of open that question; not decide it.
MR. DIONNE: If
I read the clock right, we have hit 5:00. I think we started late. I'd
like to add five minutes to the program. I just want a show of hands to
see how many people would like to join the discussion. Could we just take
the four people here? Could each of you make very quick comments and then
I'll have the
MR. SILVER: Could I just have one little response?
MR. DIONNE: Sure.
MR. SILVER: I think religion is too
narrow a term because there are people who claim to be atheists, but have
a belief in a Mother Nature that is a spiritual belief and that drives
their attitudes towards things like genetically modified crops, for
example, so religion is just one part of a larger sphere of spiritual
beliefs.
MR. DIONNE: Indeed a kind of a Mother Nature view, if you
will, a certain style of environmentalist is very much opposed to mastery
on the grounds that it distorts nature in the same way.
MR.
SILVER: Right.
MR. DIONNE: Thank you.
Sir.
JOHN
KECK: Hi. My name is John Keck. I'm actually a physicist, but I've studied
a lot of philosophy on my own. I just wanted to observe there's one thing
you need to know that without which this whole debate spins into a
hurricane, and it also makes the entire history of the 20th century and
its incredible loss of blood and all completely incomprehensible. And that
fact is that in the scientific revolution one of the babies they threw out
with the bathwater is teleology, which is the basis of ethics. And of
course the whole scientific conception of nature is it's just matter in
motion. It has no purpose, no meaning, no value beyond itself and so, it
doesn't matter if I put a bullet in your head you're just a random
agglomeration of molecules.
This is why this discussion is so
important, because science for the past, 300 years, 200 years, 100 years
has just been completely unguided by any kind of ethical principles.
There's a story about an Aeroflot flight and the pilot gets on the
intercom and he says, Comrades, I have good news and I have bad news. The
good news: we make excellent time. The bad news: we don't know where we're
going. I mean, this is America writ large. I mean, writ small.
MR.
DIONNE: Could I ask you to just get to your point? I'm sorry to do that,
but I want to bring the other folks in.
MR. KECK: Okay. Well, I
mean, I just want to say that Darwinism in general, it's not something you
want to argue for radical principle because it eliminates all ethical
principles period. And there's also a conception of evolution they don't
take it into account of more cooperative like Vidaf Kapra (ph) as a
concept of evolution.
And then also, I mean, if you look also at
the giftedness not only of who we are, but of our political beliefs a
great man wrote a couple hundred years ago, "We hold these truths to be
self-evident, that all men are created equal and endowed by their Creator
with certain inalienable rights." I would submit to you that you can't
derive liberal democracy from secular premises.
MR. DIONNE: Thank
you very much. The lady right in front there. Please. And if everybody
could stay short because I just want them to have a chance to respond.
Thank you.
CYNTHIA COHEN: I'm Cynthia Cohen from the Kennedy
Institute of Ethics at Georgetown. I was just wondering how, Professor
Sandel, you would translate your ethic of giftedness into social
regulations, laws, rules. Professor Silver was saying we live, basically,
in a society in which there's not a level playing field, so that to expect
people to voluntarily forgo enhancing their children may be asking a bit
too much from them. Would you regulate prenatal genetic diagnosis so that
parents could not select the sex of their children? Would you regulate the
use of hormones so parents could not make their kids taller if they were
basically healthy, but only of average size?
What you would be
doing in terms of social controls about this?
MR. DIONNE: Thank
you for that excellent question. I really appreciate that.
Please.
JOAN SCOTT: Joan Scott with the Genetics and Public Policy Center.
This was an excellent, excellent discussion and I thank you very much for
it. We just completed in this last year focus groups around the United
States in six locations 21 focus groups having similar conversations
with general Americans, and you don't need to be ethicists or scientists
to be able to hear these very nuanced kind of conversations like we were
hearing today being discussed by a lot of different people. And there was
this general feeling about overwhelming support for genetic technologies,
but this unease that we've been hearing about today when it comes to using
these technologies for things that are considered more frivolous. And you
hear the word vanity being used a lot and shadiness even.
And we
asked the question, If you think there should be limits set around these
technologies, who do you trust to set those limits? And people were very
troubled about who they felt should have that kind of control around the
use of these technologies. So it was a very, very interesting discussion
and occurring from a lot of different people at a lot of different levels.
MR. DIONNE: Thank you.
GARY MITCHELL: Thanks. Gary
Mitchell from the Mitchell Report. There's one of these in every session,
and I guess I'm it, but let me do it quickly. It comes from a
non-scientist. I took a college biology course in which I was introduced
to the notion of ontogeny recapitulated phylogeny and it was the only
thing I remembered, and I tried forever to sort of turn everything into
that as the metaphor.
So I'm fascinated by metaphors and in
particular the metaphor of the notion of Promethean intervention, and I
want to take it far afield and say that as I think about that metaphor and
the context in which you're discussing it here today whether it has
application in a far afield notion and I was thinking of Iraq as a
Promethean intervention and wondering whether it will lead to the, if you
will, the introduction of the gene for sustainable democracy in that part
of the world. And I don't really mean that in a partisan way, but I really
wonder whether there isn't some learning we can do about Promethean
interventions in that sense from the level in which you're thinking about
it here.
MR. DIONNE: And while we're at it, can we have a gene to
create new political parties? Because you could imagine the new line of
work for political consultants: sort of fix the election way in advance.
Can you be real fast because we are going over? Thank you.
Q: Ani Dulfig (ph) in Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics.
I wanted to bring in an aspect that hasn't really been discussed: the fact
of competition between countries. We've talked a lot about what U.S. might
try to do. What the policy what the laws American opinion, you said in
six places in America. But what about the fact that some scientists have
left the United States to work on stem lines outside the U.S.? What about
Johns Hopkins expanding the campus in Singapore their medical campus?
What about the fact that countries might attempt to use this as a
competitive advantage for whatever the purpose is?
So that's
something that needs to be included in the debate of how we want to pursue
this technology. The U.S. chose to open the nuclear Pandora's box when
faced with the danger of Nazis. We do have a future to contend with
outside the United States. It's not just our decision.
MR. DIONNE:
Thank you. So to all these very good and profound questions, you have a
few minutes to reply.
Go ahead.
MR. SANDEL: Well, a lot of
questions. On overturning teleology at the scientific revolution, that's
true, but there may be a way to bring teleology is just a big name for
purpose or end or telos, and what I'm suggesting here, and this goes back
to my attempt to respond to Bill Galston's question, I am trying to
suggest a mode of political discourse that not only makes room for
spiritual and theologically laden questions, but also with that is a
discussion of human purposes and ends, the kind of discourse that would
also be hospitable for debate about and reflection on the proper purposes,
ends, proper telos of human beings and human flourishing.
As in
response to Professor Cohen's question about what actual public policies
or regulations would flow from the kinds of concerns that I mentioned,
well, here I would tread carefully, partly because I don't have a worked
out list of regulations to propose for you, but the issue of the human
growth hormone for height enhancement was raised. Here is a case where the
FDA already regulates the use of human growth hormone and, as I mentioned,
just extended the use to go beyond the medical use but still to a very
narrow set of permissible uses. So I point to that example only to suggest
that this is not a new question, that we already do regulate not only the
practices, but also the reasons for practices, in this case height
enhancement. And I think it's sensible that we consider the reasons as
well as the practices themselves.
In the case of sex selection, I
would draw a distinction between those who want to select the sex of their
child through preimplantation of genetic diagnosis to avoid a sex-link
genetic disease. I would have no objection to that. If it became a common
practice simply for a consumer-based sex selection, then I think that
would be worrisome. What would be my public policy remedy? I don't know,
but I would probably favor discouraging it in some way or other. I don't
know what the right way to do it would be.
Consider the ads and
the donor catalogs for sperm banks and for eggs the designer egg I
mentioned. I think it might not be unreasonable if eugenic practices like
that became widespread and came to pose more of a threat than they do
today, then one thing one might do short of banning those practices,
because it's hard to delve into the reasons and the motives, would be to
say you can't advertise. You can have a commercial sperm bank, but you
can't advertise the eugenic features of the sperm you're selling. That
might be a reasonable regulation short of banning, but a way of
registering our unease with the catering to eugenic consumerism.
Cosmetic surgery is an example we have now that it exists. I don't
admire people who go in for purely elective cosmetic surgery. I don't
think it's admirable. I don't think it should be legally banned because I
don't think it's a grave enough harm, and I would certainly distinguish it
from reconstructive surgery, but here's one idea I don't even know if
I'm for it, but it's the kind of think one could discuss what about
dealing with cosmetic surgery, which is a vice it's a small vice, it's
not a grave vice, it's a small vice deal with it the way we deal with
other vices: with a sin tax. So if you go in for a purely elective
cosmetic surgery, we'll tax you and with the proceeds from that tax we
will subsidize reconstructive surgery for those who need it and can't
otherwise afford it, or other worthy things.
These are some stray
thoughts on how this ethic might embody itself in our public life.
MR. SILVER: Yeah, I'd like to make two points and then respond to
the question of where morality might be able to come from if not from
spirituality. If you go back and read Mary Shelley's Frankenstein, written
200 years ago when she was just 17 years old, there's this whole debate
about whether it's moral to cheat death and Victor Frankenstein was trying
to cheat death. In fact, that's what we do every day when we apply
medicine: We cheat death. And people overcome this initial instinct to
think that that was cheating death; meaning cheating what God intended for
you.
The second point I'd like to just tell you about because it
was a shock to me last year when I discovered it. I'm an asthmatic, which
means that I carry around this little medicine with me wherever I go, and
I discovered last year when I was teaching my course that a woman who was
in my course who was on the women's crew team at Princeton told me that 60
percent of the crew team was asthmatic. Now, I don't believe that's true.
I think that what's going on when I talked to my asthma doctor about
this is this will increase lung capacity for everyone and this is an
enhancement; so these kids are pretending that they're asthmatic and it's
a continuum and where you draw the line. It's very difficult. Of course
you can draw lines, but every line is arbitrary. It's very difficult to
draw lines.
The last point I wanted to make is where morality can
come from other than from religion, and the other answer is biology. There
was a book by Robert Wright called The Moral Animal, which suggests that
morality is encoded in our genes because it provided for a benefit a
community benefits and then the individual benefits, which is the whole
basis for liberal democracy.
MR. DIONNE: Thank you very much.
Q: (Off mike.)
MR. SILVER: Well, we have no idea how it's
encoded.
MR. DIONNE: You can continue this conversation next door,
which is what I wanted to say. I don't want to keep anyone from a drink,
ever. We are having a reception next door.
I want to close with
three things. First, The Economist magazine actually once criticized me
for writing such long acknowledgements that they ran it under the headline
"Gratitude that Grates." (Laughter.) That's true. I've always been proud
of that, in fact, but I must thank Luis of the Forum and Strobe Talbott
and Carol Graham of Brookings for being very excited as soon as this idea
was promoted. And thanks so much to Kayla Drogosz, who worked so hard on
this. Katherine Moore, Sandy Stence and all the folks at the Pew Forum.
This will be available online at www.pewforum.org and at
www.brookings.edu and I urge all religious microbiologists to write a
letter to Dr. Silver.
The last thing I want to say: One of my
favorite lines in the world is the end of Michael Sandel's book,
Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, where he makes the case for politics
by saying, "In politics we can know a good in common that we cannot know
alone." And I think they've shown today our speakers and our audience
that we can arrive at a greater wisdom in common than we ever can alone,
and I thank you all so much.
(Applause.)
(END)
Copyright © The Pew Forum on Religion & Public Life
Used on www.humanitas.org with permission of
The Pew Forum on Religion & Public Life, a project of the Pew Research Center