Print format
I Want To Burden My Loved Ones
by Gilbert Meilaender
Recently I was a speaker and panel member at a small educational
workshop on “advance directives” sponsored by the ethics committee
of our local hospital. The workshop was an opportunity to provide
information about, and discuss the relative merits of, living wills
and durable powers of attorney as different ways of trying to deal
in advance with medical decisions that might have to be made for us
after we have become incompetent. This is not the first such
workshop for me, and I suppose it may not be the last. And I was
struck, as I have been before, with the recurrence of a certain
theme.
Many
people come to such a workshop already quite knowledgeable about the
topic to be discussed. They come less for information than for the
opportunity to talk. Some earnestly desire the chance to converse
about a troubling issue; a few just want to express themselves. In
either case, however, it is remarkable how often they may say
something like the following: “I’m afraid that if my children have
to make decisions about my care, they won’t be able to handle the
pressure. They’ll just argue with each other, and they’ll feel
guilty, wondering whether they’re really doing what I would want. I
don’t want to be a burden to them, and I will do whatever I can in
advance to see that I’m not.” And after someone has spoken words to
this effect, there will be a chorus of assent from the people who,
evidently, share the speaker’s view.
Now, of
course, we can in many ways understand and appreciate such a
perspective. None of us wishes to imagine his children arguing
together about who really knows best how he should be treated (or
not treated). We hate to think that our children’s last thoughts of
us would be interwoven with anger at each other, guilt for their
uncertainty about how best to care for us, or even (perhaps) a
secret wish that we’d get on with the dying and relieve them of this
burden.
Nonetheless, as the workshop wore on, I found myself giving it only
a part of my attention, because I couldn’t help musing on this
recurring theme. Understandable as it surely is in many respects,
there is, I am convinced, something wrong with it. I don’t know how
to make the point other than a little too crassly—other than by
saying that I want to be a burden to my loved ones. But, rightly
understood, I think I do.
The
first thought that occurred to me in my musings was not, I admit,
the noblest: I have sweated in the hot sun teaching four children
to catch and hit a ball, to swing a tennis racket and shoot a free
throw. I have built blocks and played games I detest with and for
my children. I have watched countless basketball games made up
largely of bad passes, traveling violations, and shots that missed
both rim and backboard. I have sat through years of piano recitals,
band concerts, school programs—often on very busy nights or very
hot, humid evenings in late spring. I have stood in a steamy
bathroom in the middle of the night with the hot shower running,
trying to help a child with croup breathe more easily. I have run
beside a bicycle, ready to catch a child who might fall while
learning to ride. (This is, by the way, very hard!) I have spent
hours finding perfectly decent (cheap) clothing in stores, only to
have these choices rejected as somehow not exactly what we had in
mind. I have used evenings to type in final form long
stories—longer by far than necessary—that my children have written
in response to school assignments. I have had to fight for the
right to eat at Burger King rather than McDonald’s. Why should I
not be a bit of a burden to these children in my dying?
This
was not, I have already granted, the noblest thought, but it was the
first. And, of course, it overlooks a great deal—above all, that I
have taken great joy in these children and have not really resented
much in the litany of burdens recited above. But still, there is
here a serious point to be considered. Is this not in large measure
what it means to belong to a family: to burden each other—and to
find, almost miraculously, that others are willing, even happy, to
carry such burdens? Families would not have the significance they
do for us if they did not, in fact, give us a claim upon each
other. At least in this sphere of life we do not come together as
autonomous individuals freely contracting with each other. We
simply find ourselves thrown together and asked to share the burdens
of life while learning to care for each other. We may often resent
such claims on our time and energies. We did not, after all,
consent to them. (Or, at least, if we want to speak of consent, it
will have to be something like that old staple of social-contract
theorists, tacit consent.)
It is,
therefore, understandable that we sometimes chafe under these
burdens. If, however, we also go on to reject them, we cease to
live in the kind of moral community that deserves to be called a
family. Here more than in any other sphere of life we are presented
with unwanted and unexpected interruptions to our plans and
projects. I do not like such interruptions any more than the next
person; indeed, a little less, I rather suspect. But it is still
true that morality consists in large part in learning to deal with
the unwanted and unexpected interruptions to our plans. I have
tried, subject to my limits and weaknesses, to teach that lesson to
my children. Perhaps I will teach it best when I am a burden to
them in my dying.
This
was my first thought. It led to a second. Perhaps it is a good
thing, lest we be tempted to injustice, that the dying burden the
living. Some years ago Robert Burt wrote a book about medical
decision-making for incompetent patients. The book’s title was
Taking Care of Strangers. Burt’s point, which carried a
double entendre, was essentially this: Patients who are unable
to make decisions for themselves are often in a state (e.g.,
severely demented, comatose) in which they become strangers to us.
They make us uneasy, and we react with ambivalence. And to say,
“I’ll take care of him” about such a patient may be a statement
freighted with ambivalence. Burt worries that, no matter how
devoted our care, our uneasiness with a loved one who has become a
stranger to us may prompt us to do less than we ought to sustain his
life. (Nor, should we note, are physicians immune to such
uneasiness.) It is, therefore, essential that we structure the
medical decision-making situation in such a way that conversation is
forced among the doctor, the medical caregivers, the patient’s
family, and perhaps still others, such as pastor, priest, or rabbi.
Advance directives, designed to eliminate the need for such extended
conversation—lest it should burden loved ones—are, from this
perspective, somewhat problematic. They may not force us to deal
with our own ambivalence in “taking care of” a loved one who is now
a burdensome stranger.
This
does not mean that advance directives are entirely a bad idea. It
does suggest, however, that a durable power of attorney for medical
care—in which we simply name a proxy to make decisions in the event
of our incompetence—is better than a living will in which we attempt
to state the kinds of treatment we would or would not desire under a
variety of medical circumstances. At this point in my life, for
example, I would surely turn over to my wife my power of attorney.
In doing so I simply announce to medical caregivers: “Here is the
person with whom you must converse when the day comes that you
cannot talk with me about my medical care.” I myself do not
particularly like the recently fashionable attempts to combine the
two forms of advance directives by naming a proxy and giving that
proxy as much detail as possible about what we would want done.
That move—though, again, it will be seen as an attempt to avoid
burdening the loved one who must make such decisions—may not, in any
case, accomplish our aim. What it commits us to is an endless,
futile search to determine what a now-incompetent person would
wish. Still more important, it is one last-ditch attempt to bypass
the interdependence of human life, by which we simply do and should
constitute a burden to those who love us.
I hope,
therefore, that I will have the good sense to empower my wife, while
she is able, to make such decisions for me—though I know full well
that we do not always agree about what is the best care in
end-of-life circumstances. That disagreement doesn’t bother me at
all. As long as she avoids the futile question, “What would he have
wanted?” and contents herself with the (difficult enough) question,
“What is best for him now?” I will have no quarrel with her.
Moreover, this approach is, I think, less likely to encourage her to
make the moral mistake of asking, “Is his life a benefit to him
(i.e., a life worth living)?” and more likely to encourage her to
ask, “What can we do to benefit the life he still has?” No doubt
this will be a burden to her. No doubt she will bear the burden
better than I would. No doubt it will be only the last in a long
history of burdens she has borne for me. But then, mystery and
continuous miracle that it is, she loves me. And because she does,
I must of course be a burden to her.
Dr.
Gilbert Meilaender is Richard & Phyllis Duesenberg Professor of
Christian Ethics at Valparaiso University and currently serves on
the President’s Council for Bioethics.
Copyright © 1991 First Things 16 (October 1991):
12-14.
www.firstthings.com
Print format
|