Print
format
Christ and Nothing
David B.
Hart
As modern men and
women—to the degree that we are modern—we believe in nothing. This is
not to say, I hasten to add, that we do not believe in anything; I mean,
rather, that we hold an unshakable, if often unconscious, faith in the
nothing, or in nothingness as such. It is this in which we place our
trust, upon which we venture our souls, and onto which we project the
values by which we measure the meaningfulness of our lives. Or, to
phrase the matter more simply and starkly, our religion is one of very
comfortable nihilism.
This may seem a
somewhat apocalyptic note to sound, at least without any warning or
emollient prelude, but I believe I am saying nothing not almost
tediously obvious. We live in an age whose chief moral value has been
determined, by overwhelming consensus, to be the absolute liberty of
personal volition, the power of each of us to choose what he or she
believes, wants, needs, or must possess; our culturally most persuasive
models of human freedom are unambiguously voluntarist and, in a rather
debased and degraded way, Promethean; the will, we believe, is sovereign
because unpremised, free because spontaneous, and this is the highest
good. And a society that believes this must, at least implicitly,
embrace and subtly advocate a very particular moral metaphysics: the
unreality of any “value” higher than choice, or of any transcendent Good
ordering desire towards a higher end. Desire is free to propose, seize,
accept or reject, want or not want—but not to obey. Society must thus be
secured against the intrusions of the Good, or of God, so that its
citizens may determine their own lives by the choices they make from a
universe of morally indifferent but variably desirable ends,
unencumbered by any prior grammar of obligation or value (in America, we
call this the “wall of separation”). Hence the liberties that permit one
to purchase lavender bed clothes, to gaze fervently at pornography, to
become a Unitarian, to market popular celebrations of brutal violence,
or to destroy one’s unborn child are all equally intrinsically “good”
because all are expressions of an inalienable freedom of choice. But, of
course, if the will determines itself only in and through such choices,
free from any prevenient natural order, then it too is in itself
nothing. And so, at the end of modernity, each of us who is true to the
times stands facing not God, or the gods, or the Good beyond beings, but
an abyss, over which presides the empty, inviolable authority of the
individual will, whose impulses and decisions are their own moral index.
This is not to say
that—sentimental barbarians that we are—we do not still invite moral and
religious constraints upon our actions; none but the most demonic,
demented, or adolescent among us genuinely desires to live in a world
purged of visible boundaries and hospitable shelters. Thus this man may
elect not to buy a particular vehicle because he considers himself an
environmentalist; or this woman may choose not to have an abortion
midway through her second trimester, because the fetus, at that point in
its gestation, seems to her too fully formed, and she—personally—would
feel wrong about terminating “it.” But this merely illustrates my point:
we take as given the individual’s right not merely to obey or defy the
moral law, but to choose which moral standards to adopt, which values to
uphold, which fashion of piety to wear and with what accessories.
Even our ethics are
achievements of will. And the same is true of those custom-fitted
spiritualities—“New Age,” occult, pantheist, “Wiccan,” or what have
you—by which many of us now divert ourselves from the quotidien
dreariness of our lives. These gods of the boutique can come from
anywhere—native North American religion, the Indian subcontinent, some
Pre-Raphaelite grove shrouded in Celtic twilight, cunning purveyors of
otherwise worthless quartz, pages drawn at random from Robert Graves,
Aldous Huxley, Carl Jung, or that redoubtable old Aryan, Joseph
Campbell—but where such gods inevitably come to rest are not so much
divine hierarchies as ornamental étagères, where their principal office
is to provide symbolic representations of the dreamier sides of their
votaries’ personalities. The triviality of this sort of devotion, its
want of dogma or discipline, its tendency to find its divinities not in
glades and grottoes but in gift shops make it obvious that this is no
reversion to pre-Christian polytheism. It is, rather, a thoroughly
modern religion, whose burlesque gods command neither reverence, nor
dread, nor love, nor belief; they are no more than the masks worn by
that same spontaneity of will that is the one unrivalled demiurge who
rules this age and alone bids its spirits come and go.
Which brings me at last
to my topic. “I am the Lord thy God,” says the First Commandment, “Thou
shalt have no other gods before me.” For Israel this was first and
foremost a demand of fidelity, by which God bound His people to Himself,
even if in later years it became also a proclamation to the nations. To
Christians, however, the commandment came through—and so was
indissolubly bound to—Christ. As such, it was not simply a prohibition
of foreign cults, but a call to arms, an assault upon the antique order
of the heavens—a declaration of war upon the gods. All the world was to
be evangelized and baptized, all idols torn down, all worship given over
to the one God who, in these latter days, had sent His Son into the
world for our salvation. It was a long and sometimes terrible conflict,
occasionally exacting a fearful price in martyrs’ blood, but it was, by
any just estimate, a victory: the temples of Zeus and Isis alike were
finally deserted, both the paean and the dithyramb ceased to be sung,
altars were bereft of their sacrifices, the sibyls fell silent, and
ultimately all the glory, nobility, and cruelty of the ancient world lay
supine at the feet of Christ the conqueror.
Nor, for early
Christians, was this mere metaphor. When a gentile convert stood in the
baptistery on Eas-ter’s eve and, before descending naked into the
waters, turned to the West to renounce the devil and the devil’s
ministers, he was rejecting, and in fact reviling, the gods in bondage
to whom he had languished all his life; and when he turned to the East
to confess Christ, he was entrusting himself to the invincible hero who
had plundered hell of its captives, overthrown death, subdued the powers
of the air, and been raised the Lord of history. Life, for the early
Church, was spiritual warfare; and no baptized Christian could doubt how
great a transformation—of the self and the world—it was to consent to
serve no other god than Him whom Christ revealed.
We are still at war, of
course, but the situation of the Church has materially altered, and I
suspect that, by comparison to the burden the First Commandment lays
upon us today, the defeat of the ancient pantheon, and the elemental
spirits, and the demons lurking behind them will prove to have been
sublimely easy. For, as I say, we moderns believe in nothing: the
nothingness of the will miraculously giving itself form by mastering the
nothingness of the world. The gods, at least, were real, if distorted,
intimations of the mysterium tremendum, and so could inspire
something like holy dread or, occasionally, holy love. They were brutes,
obviously, but often also benign despots, and all of us I think, in
those secret corners of our souls where we are all monarchists, can
appreciate a good despot, if he is sufficiently dashing and mysterious,
and able to strike an attractive balance between capricious wrath and
serene benevolence. Certainly the Olympians had panache, and a terrible
beauty whose disappearance from the world was a bereavement to
obdurately devout pagans. Moreover, in their very objectivity and
supremacy over their worshipers, the gods gave the Church enemies with
whom it could come to grips. Perhaps they were just so many gaudy veils
and ornate brocades drawn across the abyss of night, death, and nature,
but they had distinct shapes and established cults, and when their
mysteries were abandoned, so were they.
How, though, to make
war on nothingness, on the abyss itself, denuded of its mythic allure?
It seems to me much easier to convince a man that he is in thrall to
demons and offer him manumission than to convince him that he is a slave
to himself and prisoner to his own will. Here is a god more elusive,
protean, and indomitable than either Apollo or Dionysus; and whether he
manifests himself in some demonic titanism of the will, like the mass
delirium of the Third Reich, or simply in the mesmeric banality of
consumer culture, his throne has been set in the very hearts of those he
enslaves. And it is this god, I think, against whom the First
Commandment calls us now to struggle.
There is, however, a
complication even to this. As Christians, we are glad to assert that the
commandment to have no other god, when allied to the gospel, liberated
us from the divine ancien régime; or that this same commandment must be
proclaimed again if modern persons are to be rescued from the
superstitions of our age. But there is another, more uncomfortable
assertion we should also be willing to make: that humanity could not
have passed from the devotions of antiquity to those of modernity but
for the force of Christianity in history, and so—as a matter of
historical fact—Christianity, with its cry of “no other god,” is in part
responsible for the nihilism of our culture. The gospel shook the
ancient world to its foundations, indeed tore down the heavens, and so
helped to bring us to the ruin of the present moment.
The word “nihilism” has
a complex history in modern philosophy, but I use it in a sense largely
determined by Nietzsche and Heidegger, both of whom not only diagnosed
modernity as nihilism, but saw Christianity as complicit in its genesis;
both it seems to me were penetratingly correct in some respects, if
disastrously wrong in most, and both raised questions that we Christians
ignore at our peril. Nietzsche’s case is the cruder of the two, if in
some ways the more perspicacious; for him, modernity is simply the final
phase of the disease called Christianity. Whereas the genius of the
Greeks—so his story goes—was to gaze without illusion into the chaos and
terror of the world, and respond not with fear or resignation but with
affirmation and supreme artistry, they were able to do this only on
account of their nobility, which means their ruthless willingness to
discriminate between the “good”—that is, the strength, exuberance,
bravery, generosity, and harshness of the aristocratic spirit—and the
“bad”—the weakness, debility, timorousness, and vindictive resentfulness
of the slavish mind. And this same standard—“noble wisdom,” for want of
a better term—was the foundation and mortar of Roman civilization.
Christianity, however,
was a slave revolt in morality: the cunning of the weak triumphed over
the nobility of the strong, the resentment of the many converted the
pride of the few into self-torturing guilt, the higher man’s distinction
between the good and the bad was replaced by the lesser man’s spiteful
distinction between good and “evil,” and the tragic wisdom of the Greeks
sank beneath the flood of Christianity’s pity and pusillanimity. This
revolt, joined to an ascetic and sterile devotion to positive fact,
would ultimately slay even God. And, as a result, we have now entered
the age of the Last Men, whom Nietzsche depicts in terms too close for
comfort to the banality, conformity, and self-indulgence of modern mass
culture.
Heidegger’s tale is not
as catastrophist, and so emphasizes less Christianity’s novelty than its
continuity with a nihilism implicit in all Western thought, from at
least the time of Plato (which Nietzsche, in his way, also
acknowledged). Nihilism, says Heidegger, is born in a forgetfulness of
the mystery of being, and in the attempt to capture and master being in
artifacts of reason (the chief example—and indeed the prototype of every
subsequent apostasy from true “ontology”—being Plato’s ideas).
Scandalously to oversimplify his argument, it is, says Heidegger, the
history of this nihilistic impulse to reduce being to an object of the
intellect, subject to the will, that has brought us at last to the age
of technology, for which reality is just so many quanta of power, the
world a representation of consciousness, and the earth a mere reserve
awaiting exploitation; technological mastery has become our highest
ideal, and our only real model of truth. Christianity, for its part, is
not so much a new thing as a prolonged episode within the greater
history of nihilism, notable chiefly for having brought part of this
history’s logic to its consummation by having invented the metaphysical
God, the form of all forms, who grounds all of being in himself as
absolute efficient cause, and who personifies that cause as total power
and will. From this God, in the fullness of time, would be born the
modern subject who has usurped God’s place.
I hope I will be
excused both for so cursory a précis and for the mild perversity that
causes me to see some merit in both of these stories. Heidegger seems to
me obviously correct in regarding modernity’s nihilism as the fruition
of seeds sown in pagan soil; and Nietzsche also correct to call
attention to Christianity’s shocking—and, for the antique order of noble
values, irreparably catastrophic—novelty; but neither grasped why he was
correct. For indeed Christianity was complicit in the death of antiquity
and in the birth of modernity, not because it was an accomplice of the
latter, but because it alone, in the history of the West, was a
rejection of and alternative to nihilism’s despair, violence, and
idolatry of power; as such, Christianity shattered the imposing and
enchanting façade behind which nihilism once hid, and thereby,
inadvertently, called it forth into the open.
I am speaking
(impressionistically, I grant) of something pervasive in the ethos of
European antiquity, which I would call a kind of glorious sadness. The
great Indo-European mythos, from which Western culture sprang, was
chiefly one of sacrifice: it understood the cosmos as a closed system, a
finite totality, within which gods and mortals alike occupied places
determined by fate. And this totality was, of necessity, an economy, a
cycle of creation and destruction, oscillating between order and chaos,
form and indeterminacy: a great circle of feeding, preserving life
through a system of transactions with death. This is the myth of
“cosmos”—of the universe as a precarious equilibrium of contrary
forces—which undergirded a sacral practice whose aim was to contain
nature’s promiscuous violence within religion’s orderly violence. The
terrible dynamism of nature had to be both resisted and controlled by
rites at once apotropaic—appeasing chaos and rationalizing it within the
stability of cult—and economic—recuperating its sacrificial expenditures
in the form of divine favor, a numinous power reinforcing the regime
that sacrifice served. And this regime was, naturally, a fixed hierarchy
of social power, atop which stood the gods, a little lower kings and
nobles, and at the bottom slaves; the order of society, both divine and
natural in provenance, was a fixed and yet somehow fragile “hierarchy
within totality” that had to be preserved against the forces that
surrounded it, while yet drawing on those forces for its spiritual
sustenance. Gods and mortals were bound together by necessity; we fed
the gods, who required our sacrifices, and they preserved us from the
forces they personified and granted us some measure of their power.
There was, surely, an ineradicable nihilism in such an economy: a tragic
resignation before fate, followed by a prudential act of cultic salvage,
for the sake of social and cosmic stability.
As it happens, the word
“tragic” is especially apt here. A sacrificial mythos need not always
express itself in slaughter, after all. Attic tragedy, for instance,
began as a sacrificial rite. It was performed during the festival of
Dionysus, which was a fertility festival, of course, but only because it
was also an apotropaic celebration of delirium and death: the Dionysia
was a sacred negotiation with the wild, antinomian cruelty of the god
whose violent orgiastic cult had once, so it was believed, gravely
imperiled the city; and the hope that prompted the feast was that, if
this devastating force could be contained within bright Apollonian forms
and propitiated through a ritual carnival of controlled disorder, the
polis could survive for another year, its precarious peace intact.
The religious vision
from which Attic tragedy emerged was one of the human community as a
kind of besieged citadel preserving itself through the tribute it paid
to the powers that both threatened and enlivened it. I can think of no
better example of this than that of Antigone, in which the tragic
crisis is the result of an insoluble moral conflict between familial
piety (a sacred obligation) and the civil duties of kingship (a holy
office): Antigone, as a woman, is bound to the chthonian gods (gods of
the dead, so of family and household), and Creon, as king, is bound to
Apollo (god of the city), and so both are adhering to sacred
obligations. The conflict between them, then, far from involving a
tension between the profane and the holy, is a conflict within the
divine itself, whose only possible resolution is the death—the
sacrifice—of the protagonist. Other examples, however, are legion.
Necessity’s cruel intransigence rules the gods no less than us;
tragedy’s great power is simply to reconcile us to this truth, to what
must be, and to the violences of the city that keep at bay the greater
violence of cosmic or social disorder.
Nor does one require
extraordinarily penetrating insight to see how the shadow of this mythos
falls across the philosophical schools of antiquity. To risk a
generalization even more reckless than those I have already made: from
the time of the pre-Socratics, all the great speculative and moral
systems of the pagan world were, in varying degrees, confined to this
totality, to either its innermost mechanisms or outermost boundaries;
rarely did any of them catch even a glimpse of what might lie beyond
such a world; and none could conceive of reality except as a kind of
strife between order and disorder, within which a sacrificial economy
held all forces in tension. This is true even of Platonism, with its
inextirpable dualism, its dialectic of change and the changeless (or of
limit and the infinite), and its equation of truth with eidetic
abstraction; the world, for all its beauty, is the realm of fallen
vision, separated by a great chorismos from the realm of
immutable reality.
It is true of Aristotle
too: the dialectic of act and potency that, for sublunary beings, is
inseparable from decay and death, or the scale of essences by which all
things—especially various classes of persons—are assigned their places
in the natural and social order. Stoicism offers an obvious example: a
vision of the universe as a fated, eternally repeated divine and cosmic
history, a world in which finite forms must constantly perish simply in
order to make room for others, and which in its entirety is always
consumed in a final ecpyrosis (which makes a sacrificial pyre, so
to speak, of the whole universe). And Neoplatonism furnishes the most
poignant example, inasmuch as its monism merely inverts earlier
Platonism’s dualism and only magnifies the melancholy. Not only is the
mutable world separated from its divine principle—the One—by intervals
of emanation that descend in ever greater alienation from their source,
but because the highest truth is the secret identity between the human
mind and the One, the labor of philosophy is one of escape: all
multiplicity, change, particularity, every feature of the living world,
is not only accidental to this formless identity, but a kind of
falsehood, and to recover the truth that dwells within, one must detach
oneself from what lies without, including the sundry incidentals of
one’s individual existence; truth is oblivion of the flesh, a pure
nothingness, to attain which one must sacrifice the world.
In any event, the
purpose behind these indefensibly broad pronouncements—however
elliptically pursued—is to aid in recalling how shatteringly subversive
Christianity was of so many of the certitudes of the world it entered,
and how profoundly its exclusive fidelity to the God of Christ
transformed that world. This is, of course, no more than we should
expect, if we take the New Testament’s Paschal triumphalism to heart:
“Now is the judgment of this world, now will the prince of this world be
cast out” (John 12:31); “I have overcome the world” (John 16:33); he is
“far above all principality, and power, and might, and dominion” and all
things are put “under his feet” (Ephesians 1:21-2); “having spoiled
principalities and powers, he made a show of them openly, triumphing
over them in it” (Colossians 2:15); “he led captivity captive”
(Ephesians 4:8); and so on. Still, we can largely absorb Scripture’s
talk of the defeat of the devil, the angels of the nations, and the
powers of the air, and yet fail to recognize how radically the Gospels
reinterpreted (or, as Nietzsche would say, “transvalued”) everything in
the light of Easter.
The example of this I
find most striking is the account John’s Gospel gives of the dialogue
between Christ and Pilate (John 18:28-19:12). Nietzsche, the quixotic
champion of the old standards, thought jesting Pilate’s “What is truth?”
to be the only moment of actual nobility in the New Testament, the wry
taunt of an acerbic ironist unimpressed by the pathetic fantasies of a
deranged peasant. But one need not share Nietzsche’s sympathies to take
his point; one can certainly see what is at stake when Christ, scourged
and mocked, is brought before Pilate a second time: the latter’s “Whence
art thou?” has about it something of a demand for a pedigree, which
might at least lend some credibility to the claims Christ makes for
himself; for want of which, Pilate can do little other than pronounce
his truth: “I have power to crucify thee” (which, to be fair, would
under most circumstances be an incontrovertible argument).
It is worth asking
ourselves what this tableau, viewed from the vantage of pagan antiquity,
would have meant. A man of noble birth, representing the power of Rome,
endowed with authority over life and death, confronted by a barbarous
colonial of no name or estate, a slave of the empire, beaten, robed in
purple, crowned with thorns, insanely invoking an otherworldly kingdom
and some esoteric truth, unaware of either his absurdity or his judge’s
eminence. Who could have doubted where, between these two, the truth of
things was to be found? But the Gospel is written in the light of the
resurrection, which reverses the meaning of this scene entirely. If
God’s truth is in fact to be found where Christ stands, the mockery
visited on him redounds instead upon the emperor, all of whose regal
finery, when set beside the majesty of the servile shape in which God
reveals Himself, shows itself to be just so many rags and briars.
This slave is the
Father’s eternal Word, whom God has vindicated, and so ten thousand
immemorial certainties are unveiled as lies: the first become last, the
mighty are put down from their seats and the lowly exalted, the hungry
are filled with good things while the rich are sent empty away.
Nietzsche was quite right to be appalled. Almost as striking, for me, is
the tale of Peter, at the cock’s crow, going apart to weep. Nowhere in
the literature of pagan antiquity, I assure you, had the tears of a
rustic been regarded as worthy of anything but ridicule; to treat them
with reverence, as meaningful expressions of real human sorrow, would
have seemed grotesque from the perspective of all the classical canons
of good taste. Those wretchedly subversive tears, and the dangerous
philistinism of a narrator so incorrigibly vulgar as to treat them with
anything but contempt, were most definitely signs of a slave revolt in
morality, if not quite the one against which Nietzsche inveighed—a
revolt, moreover, that all the ancient powers proved impotent to resist.
In a narrow sense,
then, one might say that the chief offense of the Gospels is their
defiance of the insights of tragedy—and not only because Christ does not
fit the model of the well-born tragic hero. More important is the
incontestable truth that, in the Gospels, the destruction of the
protagonist emphatically does not restore or affirm the order of city or
cosmos. Were the Gospels to end with Christ’s sepulture, in good tragic
style, it would exculpate all parties, including Pilate and the
Sanhedrin, whose judgments would be shown to have been fated by the
exigencies of the crisis and the burdens of their offices; the story
would then reconcile us to the tragic necessity of all such judgments.
But instead comes Easter, which rudely interrupts all the minatory and
sententious moralisms of the tragic chorus, just as they are about to be
uttered to full effect, and which cavalierly violates the central tenet
of sound economics: rather than trading the sacrificial victim for some
supernatural benefit, and so the particular for the universal, Easter
restores the slain hero in his particularity again, as the only truth
the Gospels have to offer. This is more than a dramatic peripety. The
empty tomb overturns all the “responsible” and “necessary” verdicts of
Christ’s judges, and so grants them neither legitimacy nor pardon.
In a larger sense,
then, the entire sacrificial logic of a culture was subverted in the
Gospels. I cannot attempt here a treatment of the biblical language of
sacrifice, but I think I can safely assert that Christ’s death does not,
in the logic of the New Testament sources, fit the pattern of sacrifice
I have just described. The word “sacrifice” is almost inexhaustible in
its polysemy, particularly in the Old Testament, but the only
sacrificial model explicitly invoked in the New Testament is that of the
Atonement offering of Israel, which certainly belongs to no cosmic cycle
of prudent expenditure and indemnity. It is, rather, a qurban,
literally a “drawing nigh” into the life-giving presence of God’s glory.
Israel’s God requires nothing; He creates, elects, and sanctifies
without need—and so the Atonement offering can in no way contribute to
any sort of economy. It is instead a penitent approach to a God who
gives life freely, and who not only does not profit from the holocaust
of the particular, but who in fact fulfils the “sacrifice” simply by
giving his gift again. This giving again is itself, in fact, a kind of
“sacrificial” motif in Hebrew Scripture, achieving its most powerful
early expression in the story of Isaac’s aqedah, and arriving at
its consummation, perhaps, in Ezekiel’s vision in the valley of dry
bones. After all, a people overly burdened by the dolorous superstitions
of tragic wisdom could never have come to embrace the doctrine of
resurrection.
I am tempted to say,
then, that the cross of Christ is not simply a sacrifice, but the place
where two opposed understandings of sacrifice clashed. Christ’s whole
life was a reconciling qurban: an approach to the Father, a real
indwelling of God’s glory in the temple of Christ’s body, and an
atonement made for a people enslaved to death. In pouring himself out in
the form of a servant, and in living his humanity as an offering up of
everything to God in love, the shape of the eternal Son’s life was
already sacrificial in this special sense; and it was this absolute
giving, as God and man, that was made complete on Golgotha. While, from
a pagan perspective, the crucifixion itself could be viewed as a
sacrifice in the most proper sense—destruction of the agent of social
instability for the sake of peace, which is always a profitable
exchange—Christ’s life of charity, service, forgiveness, and righteous
judgment could not; indeed, it would have to seem the very opposite of
sacrifice, an aneconomic and indiscriminate inversion of rank and order.
Yet, at Easter, it is the latter that God accepts and the former He
rejects; what, then, of all the hard-won tragic wisdom of the ages?
Naturally, also, with
the death of the old mythos, metaphysics too was transformed. For one
thing, while every ancient system of philosophy had to presume an
economy of necessity binding the world of becoming to its inmost or
highest principles, Christian theology taught from the first that the
world was God’s creature in the most radically ontological sense: that
it is called from nothingness, not out of any need on God’s part, but by
grace. The world adds nothing to the being of God, and so nothing need
be sacrificed for His glory or sustenance. In a sense, God and world
alike were liberated from the fetters of necessity; God could be
accorded His true transcendence and the world its true character as
divine gift. The full implications of this probably became visible to
Christian philosophers only with the resolution of the fourth-century
trinitarian controversies, when the subordinationist schemes of
Alexandrian trinitarianism were abandoned, and with them the last
residue within theology of late Platonism’s vision of a descending scale
of divinity mediating between God and world—the both of them comprised
in a single totality.
In any event, developed
Christian theology rejected nothing good in the metaphysics, ethics, or
method of ancient philosophy, but—with a kind of omnivorous
glee—assimilated such elements as served its ends, and always improved
them in the process. Stoic morality, Plato’s language of the Good,
Aristotle’s metaphysics of act and potency—all became richer and more
coherent when emancipated from the morbid myths of sacrificial economy
and tragic necessity. In truth, Christian theology nowhere more wantonly
celebrated its triumph over the old gods than in the use it made of the
so-called spolia Aegyptorum; and, by despoiling pagan philosophy
of its most splendid achievements and integrating them into a vision of
reality more complete than philosophy could attain on its own, theology
took to itself irrevocably all the intellectual glories of antiquity.
The temples were stripped of their gold and precious ornaments, the
sacred vessels were carried away into the precincts of the Church and
turned to better uses, and nothing was left behind but a few grim, gaunt
ruins to lure back the occasional disenchanted Christian and shelter a
few atavistic ghosts.
This last observation
returns me at last to my earlier contention: that Christianity assisted
in bringing the nihilism of modernity to pass. The command to have no
other god but Him whom Christ revealed was never for Christians simply
an invitation to forsake an old cult for a new, but was an announcement
that the shape of the world had changed, from the depths of hell to the
heaven of heavens, and all nations were called to submit to Jesus as
Lord. In the great “transvaluation” that followed, there was no sphere
of social, religious, or intellectual life that the Church did not claim
for itself; much was abolished, and much of the grandeur and beauty of
antiquity was preserved in a radically altered form, and Christian
civilization—with its new synthesis and new creativity—was born.
But what is the
consequence, then, when Christianity, as a living historical force,
recedes? We have no need to speculate, as it happens; modernity speaks
for itself: with the withdrawal of Christian culture, all the glories of
the ancient world that it baptized and redeemed have perished with it in
the general cataclysm. Christianity is the midwife of nihilism, not
because it is itself nihilistic, but because it is too powerful in its
embrace of the world and all of the world’s mystery and beauty; and so
to reject Christianity now is, of necessity, to reject everything except
the barren anonymity of spontaneous subjectivity. As Ivan Karamazov’s
Grand Inquisitor tells Christ, the freedom that the gospel brings is too
terrible to be borne indefinitely. Our sin makes us feeble and craven,
and we long to flee from the liberty of the sons of God; but where now
can we go? Everything is Christ’s.
This is illustrated
with striking clarity by the history of modern philosophy, at least in
its continental (and, so to speak, proper) form. It is fashionable at
present, among some theologians, to attempt precise genealogies of
modernity, which in general I would rather avoid doing; but it does seem
clear to me that the special preoccupations and perversities of modern
philosophy were incubated in the age of late Scholasticism, with the
rise of nominalism and voluntarism. Whereas earlier theology spoke of
God as Goodness as such, whose every act (by virtue of divine
simplicity) expresses His nature, the spectre that haunts late
Scholastic thought is a God whose will precedes His nature, and whose
acts then are feats of pure spontaneity. It is a logically incoherent
way of conceiving of God, as it happens (though I cannot argue that
here), but it is a powerful idea, elevating as it does will over all
else and redefining freedom—for God and, by extension, for us—not as the
unhindered realization of a nature (the liberty to “become what you
are”), but as the absolute liberty of the will in determining even what
its nature is.
Thus when modern
philosophy established itself anew as a discipline autonomous from
theology, it did so naturally by falling back upon an ever more abyssal
subjectivity. Real autonomy could not be gained by turning back to the
wonder of being or to the transcendental perfections of the world, for
to do so would be to slip again into a sphere long colonized by
theology. And so the new point of departure for reason had to be the
perceiving subject rather than the world perceived. Descartes, for
instance, explicitly forbade himself any recourse to the world’s
testimony of itself; in his third Meditation, he seals all his senses
against nature, so that he can undertake his rational reconstruction of
reality from a position pure of any certitude save that of the ego’s own
existence. The world is recovered thereafter only insofar as it is
“posited,” as an act of will. And while God appears in that
reconstruction, He does so only as a logical postulate following from
the idea of the infinite.
From there, it is a
short step to Kant’s transcendental ego, for whom the world is the
representation of its own irreducible “I think,” and which (inasmuch as
it is its own infinity) requires God as a postulate only in the realm of
ethics, and merely as a regulative idea in the realm of epistemology.
And the passage from transcendental idealism to absolute idealism,
however much it involved an attempt to escape egoistic subjectivity, had
no world to which to return. Even Hegel’s system, for all that it sought
to have done with petty subjectivism, could do so only by way of a
massive metaphysical myth of the self-positing of the Concept, and of a
more terrible economy of necessity than any pagan antiquity had
imagined. This project was, in every sense, incredible, and its collapse
inevitably brought philosophy, by way of Nietzsche and Heidegger, to its
“postmodern condition”—a “heap of broken images.” If Heidegger was
right—and he was—in saying that there was always a nihilistic core to
the Western philosophical tradition, the withdrawal of Christianity
leaves nothing but that core behind, for the gospel long ago stripped
away both the deceits and the glories that had concealed it; and so
philosophy becomes, almost by force of habit, explicit nihilism.
Modern philosophy,
however, merely reflects the state of modern culture and modern cult;
and it is to this sphere that I should turn now, as it is here that
spiritual warfare is principally to be waged.
I should admit that I,
for one, feel considerable sympathy for Nietzsche’s plaint, “Nearly
two-thousand years and no new god”—and for Heidegger intoning his
mournful oracle: “Only a god can save us.” But of course none will come.
The Christian God has taken up everything into Himself; all the
treasures of ancient wisdom, all the splendor of creation, every good
thing has been assumed into the story of the incarnate God, and every
stirring towards transcendence is soon recognized by the modern
mind—weary of God—as leading back towards faith. Antique pieties cannot
be restored, for we moderns know that the hungers they excite can be
sated only by the gospel of Christ and him crucified. To be a Stoic
today, for instance, is simply to be a soul in via to the Church; a
Platonist, most of us understand, is only a Christian manqué; and a
polytheist is merely a truant from the one God he hates and loves.
The only cult that can
truly thrive in the aftermath of Christianity is a sordid service of the
self, of the impulses of the will, of the nothingness that is all that
the withdrawal of Christianity leaves behind. The only futures open to
post-Christian culture are conscious nihilism, with its inevitable
devotion to death, or the narcotic banality of the Last Men, which may
be little better than death. Surveying the desert of modernity, we would
be, I think, morally derelict not to acknowledge that Nietzsche was
right in holding Christianity responsible for the catastrophe around us
(even if he misunderstood why); we should confess that the failure of
Christian culture to live up to its victory over the old gods has
allowed the dark power that once hid behind them to step forward in
propria persona. And we should certainly dread whatever rough beast
it is that is being bred in our ever coarser, crueler, more
inarticulate, more vacuous popular culture; because, cloaked in its
anodyne insipience, lies a world increasingly devoid of merit, wit,
kindness, imagination, or charity.
These are, I admit,
extreme formulations. But, while I may delight in provocation, I do not
wish on this point to be misunderstood. When recently I made these very
remarks from a speaker’s podium, two theologians (neither of whom I
would consider a champion of modernity) raised objections. From one
quarter, I was chided for forgetting the selflessness of which modern
persons are capable. September 11, 2001, I was reminded, demonstrated
the truth of this, surely; and those of us who teach undergraduates must
be aware that, for all the cultural privations they suffer, they are
often decent and admirable. From the other quarter I was cautioned that
so starkly stated an alternative as “Christianity or nihilism” amounted
to a denial of the goodness of natural wisdom and virtue, and seemed to
suggest that gratia non perficit, sed destruit naturam. As fair
as such remarks may be, however, they are not apposite to my argument.
In regard to the first
objection, I would wish to reply by making clear that I do not intend to
suggest that, because modernity has lost the organic integrity of
Christianity’s moral grammar, every person living in modern society must
therefore become heartless, violent, or unprincipled. My observations
are directed at the dominant language and ethos of a culture, not at the
souls of individuals. Many among us retain some loyalty to ancient
principles, most of us are in some degree premodern, and there are
always and everywhere to be found examples of natural virtue, innate
nobility, congenital charity, and so on, for the light of God is
ubiquitous and the image of God is impressed upon our nature. The issue
for me is whether, within the moral grammar of modernity, any of these
good souls could give an account of his or her virtue.
I wish, that is, to
make a point not conspicuously different from Alasdair MacIntyre’s in
the first chapter of his After Virtue: in the wake of a morality
of the Good, ethics has become a kind of incoherent bricolage. As far as
I can tell, homo nihilisticus may often be in several notable
respects a far more amiable rogue than homo religiosus,
exhibiting a far smaller propensity for breaking the crockery,
destroying sacred statuary, or slaying the nearest available infidel.
But, love, let us be true to one another: even when all of this is
granted, it would be a willful and culpable blindness for us to refuse
to recognize how aesthetically arid, culturally worthless, and
spiritually depraved our society has become. That this is not hyperbole
a dispassionate appraisal of the artifacts of popular culture—of the
imaginative coarseness and cruelty informing them—will quickly confirm.
For me, it is enough to consider that, in America alone, more than forty
million babies have been aborted since the Supreme Court invented the
“right” that allows for this, and that there are many for whom this is
viewed not even as a tragic “necessity,” but as a triumph of moral
truth. When the Carthaginians were prevailed upon to cease sacrificing
their babies, at least the place vacated by Baal reminded them that they
should seek the divine above themselves; we offer up our babies to “my”
freedom of choice, to “me.” No society’s moral vision has ever, surely,
been more degenerate than that.
And to the second
objection, I would begin by noting that my remarks here do not concern
the entirety of human experience, nature, or culture; they concern one
particular location in time and space: late Western modernity. Nor have
I anything to say about cultures or peoples who have not suffered the
history of faith and disenchantment we have, or who do not share our
particular relation to European antiquity or the heritage of ancient
Christendom. “Nihilism” is simply a name for post-Christian sensibility
and conviction (and not even an especially opprobrious one). Moreover,
the alternative between Christianity and nihilism is never, in actual
practice, a kind of Kierkegaardian either/or posed between two absolute
antinomies, incapable of alloy or medium; it is an antagonism that
occurs along a continuum, whose extremes are rarely perfectly expressed
in any single life (else the world were all saints and satanists).
Most importantly,
though, my observations do not concern nature at all, which is
inextinguishable and which, at some level, always longs for God; they
concern culture, which has the power to purge itself of the natural in
some considerable degree. Indeed, much of the discourse of late
modernity—speculative, critical, moral, and political—consists precisely
in an attempt to deny the authority, or even the reality, of any general
order of nature or natures. Nature is good, I readily affirm, and is
itself the first gift of grace. But that is rather the point at issue:
for modernity is unnatural, is indeed anti-nature, or even anti-Christ
(and so goeth about as a roaring lion, seeking whom it may devour).
Which is why I repeat
that our age is not one in danger of reverting to paganism (would that
we were so fortunate). If we turn from Christ today, we turn only
towards the god of absolute will, and embrace him under either his most
monstrous or his most vapid aspect. A somewhat more ennobling retreat to
the old gods is not possible for us; we can find no shelter there, nor
can we sink away gently into those old illusions and tragic consolations
that Christ has exposed as falsehoods. To love or be nourished by the
gods, we would have to fear them; but the ruin of their glory is so
complete that they have been reduced—like everything else—to
commodities.
Nor will the ululations
and lugubrious platitudes and pious fatalism of the tragic chorus ever
again have the power to recall us to sobriety. The gospel of a God found
in broken flesh, humility, and measureless charity has defeated all the
old lies, rendered the ancient order visibly insufficient and even
slightly absurd, and instilled in us a longing for transcendent love so
deep that—if once yielded to—it will never grant us rest anywhere but in
Christ. And there is a real sadness in this, because the consequences of
so great a joy rejected are a sorrow, bewilderment, and anxiety for
which there is no precedent. If the nonsensical religious fascinations
of today are not, in any classical or Christian sense, genuine pieties,
they are nevertheless genuine—if deluded—expressions of grief, encomia
for a forsaken and half-forgotten home, the prisoner’s lament over a
lost freedom. For Christians, then, to recover and understand the
meaning of the command to have “no other god,” it is necessary first to
recognize that the victory of the Church in history was not only
incomplete, but indeed set free a force that the old sacral order had at
least been able to contain; and it is against this more formless and
invincible enemy that we take up the standard of the commandment today.
Moreover, we need to
recognize, in the light of this history, that this commandment is a hard
discipline: it destroys, it breaks in order to bind; like a cautery, it
wounds in order to heal; and now, in order to heal the damage it has in
part inflicted, it must be applied again. In practical terms, I suspect
that this means that Christians must make an ever more concerted effort
to recall and recover the wisdom and centrality of the ascetic
tradition. It takes formidable faith and devotion to resist the evils of
one’s age, and it is to the history of Christian asceticism—especially,
perhaps, the apophthegms of the Desert Fathers—that all Christians,
whether married or not, should turn for guidance. To have no god but the
God of Christ, after all, means today that we must endure the lenten
privations of what is most certainly a dark age, and strive to resist
the bland solace, inane charms, brute viciousness, and dazed passivity
of post-Christian culture—all of which are so tempting precisely because
they enjoin us to believe in and adore ourselves.
It means also to remain
aloof from many of the moral languages of our time, which are—even at
their most sentimental, tender, and tolerant—usually as decadent and
egoistic as the currently most fashionable vices. It means, in short,
self-abnegation, contrarianism, a willingness not only to welcome but to
condemn, and a refusal of secularization as fierce as the refusal of our
Christian ancestors to burn incense to the genius of the emperor. This
is not an especially grim prescription, I should add: Christian
asceticism is not, after all, a cruel disfigurement of the will,
contaminated by the world-weariness or malice towards creation that one
can justly ascribe to many other varieties of religious detachment. It
is, rather, the cultivation of the pure heart and pure eye, which allows
one to receive the world, and rejoice in it, not as a possession of the
will or an occasion for the exercise of power, but as the good gift of
God. It is, so to speak, a kind of “Marian” waiting upon the Word of God
and its fruitfulness. This is why it has the power to heal us of our
modern derangements: because, paradoxical as it may seem to modern
temperaments, Christian asceticism is the practice of love, what Maximus
the Confessor calls learning to see the logos of each thing within the
Logos of God, and it eventuates most properly in the grateful reverence
of a Bonaventure or the lyrical ecstasy of a Thomas Traherne.
Still, it is a
discipline for all that; and for us today it must involve the painful
acknowledgement that neither we nor our distant progeny will live to see
a new Christian culture rise in the Western world, and to accept this
with both charity and faith. We must, after all, grant that, in the
mystery of God’s providence, all of this has followed from the work of
the Holy Spirit in time. Modern persons will never find rest for their
restless hearts without Christ, for modern culture is nothing but the
wasteland from which the gods have departed, and so this restlessness
has become its own deity; and, deprived of the shelter of the sacred and
the consoling myths of sacrifice, the modern person must wander or
drift, vainly attempting one or another accommodation with death, never
escaping anxiety or ennui, and driven as a result to a ceaseless labor
of distraction, or acquisition, or willful idiocy. And, where it works
its sublimest magic, our culture of empty spectacle can so stupefy the
intellect as to blind it to its own disquiet, and induce a spiritual
torpor more deplorable than mere despair.
But we Christians—while
not ignoring how appalling such a condition is—should yet rejoice that
modernity offers no religious comforts to those who would seek them. In
this time of waiting, in this age marked only by the absence of faith in
Christ, it is well that the modern soul should lack repose, piety,
peace, or nobility, and should find the world outside the Church barren
of spiritual rapture or mystery, and should discover no beautiful or
terrible or merciful gods upon which to cast itself. With Christ came
judgment into the world, a light of discrimination from which there is
neither retreat nor sanctuary. And this means that, as a quite concrete
historical condition, the only choice that remains for the children of
post-Christian culture is not whom to serve, but whether to serve Him
whom Christ has revealed or to serve nothing—the nothing. No
third way lies open for us now, because—as all of us now know, whether
we acknowledge it consciously or not—all things have been made subject
to Him, all the thrones and dominions of the high places have been put
beneath His feet, until the very end of the world, and—simply said—there
is no other god.
David B. Hart
is an Eastern Orthodox theologian. The original version of this article
was delivered as a lecture at a conference on the Ten Commandments held
at St. Olaf’s College in Northfield, Minnesota, June 15-17, under the
joint sponsorship of the Center for Catholic and Evangelical Theology
and the Society for Ecumenical Anglican Doctrine. The papers from this
conference will be published by Eerdmans.
Copyright © 2003 First Things 136
(October 2003): 47-57.
www.firstthings.com
Posted with permission on
www.humanitas.org.
Print
format
|