Print
format
Altering the Face of Humanity
Life, Liberty, and the
Defense of Human Dignity: The Challenge of Bioethics.
By Leon R. Kass. Encounter. 300 pp. $26.95.
Reviewed by Marc D. Guerra
Leon Kass has
described himself as a strange man who writes strange and
untimely books. Given the intellectual condition of the
contemporary academy, this is by no means a bad thing.
Trained professionally as a physician and biochemist, Kass
has, without formal academic training, taught courses in
philosophy and literature for the past twenty–eight years at
the University of Chicago. A prolific essayist, he has
published books on the proper relation of biology and human
affairs, the connection between eating and the perfection of
human nature, and the deepest meanings of courtship and
marriage. But the real reason why Kass seems so strange
today is that he defends the dignity of our given human
nature in a world that is transformed almost daily by
advances in science and technology.
Life,
Liberty, and the Defense of Dignity is largely a
collection of reworked, previously published essays on
biotechnology—one of which originally appeared in First
Things (“L’Chaim and Its Limits: Why Not Immortality?” May
2001). In this book, the Chairman of the President’s Council
on Bioethics offers a penetrating and unnerving reflection
on how biotechnology’s growing ability to alter our nature
fundamentally threatens our dignity as human beings.
Biotechnology is, as Kass shows, something of a mixed
blessing. It has allowed many of us to live longer and
healthier lives, something Kass believes we should be most
grateful for. At the same time, some emerging
biotechnologies—especially in neuroscience and
psychopharmacology—threaten to technologically alter the
very face of our humanity. As Kass jarringly puts it in his
Introduction, the burgeoning biotech revolution has already
brought us to a point where “human nature itself lies on the
operating table, ready for alteration, for eugenic and
neuropsychic ‘enhancement,’ for wholesale redesign.”
In Kass’
view, this kind of technological enhancement and redesign
ultimately will result in the flattening of our souls. By
pursuing physical health as the greatest of human goods, we
will inevitably end up sacrificing the moral and spiritual
goods that give meaning and dignity to our lives. The
degraded and dehumanized “Brave New World” of soma and
Bokanovskification that Aldous Huxley so vividly described
two generations ago seems closer with each passing day.
Western
societies have largely been unwilling to face the
all–too–human consequences of this looming posthuman
future. Seduced by promises of even bigger and better
biotechnologies in the years to come, we have opted not to
think about what is really at stake in the biotech
revolution. However, given the recent extraordinary
proliferation of biotechnologies, from the completion of the
Human Genome Project to our growing expertise in the science
of cloning, the time has come for everyone who cares about
the preservation of our humanity to recognize what is at
stake. In this effort, Kass’ elegantly written and
thought–provoking book will undoubtedly be of much help.
Kass begins
his book with a reflection on “the problem of technology and
liberal democracy.” The two have something of a symbiotic
relationship. On the one hand, genuine technological
progress presupposes the kind of intellectual and economic
freedom that liberal democracy secures. On the other,
liberal societies must rely upon technology for assistance
in everything from supplying healthy and affordable foods,
to sustaining great numbers of people, to developing new and
improved military technologies. But technology also creates
its own set of problems. Take the case of medical science’s
increased ability to push back the frontiers of death. As
medical science has helped us live healthier and longer
lives, our society has had to struggle to figure out how to
take care of a citizenry whose longevity continually
increases. Like so many other things in life, technological
“progress” is not immune to the law of unintended
consequences.
That we view
technology as a “problem” at all shows the remarkable extent
to which we have internalized modern science’s mechanized
and reductionist account of the world. As Kass shows, the
greatest problem posed by today’s “brave new biology” does
not come from the technologies it produces, but rather from
the scientific view from which it is derived. To understand
just how deep the problem of biotechnology runs, Kass points
out, it must be viewed in the larger context of the
revolutionary character of modern science.
Building on
the analysis of thinkers such as Leo Strauss and Hans Jonas,
Kass offers a rich reflection on the “philosophical
foundations” of modern science. The philosophical architects
of modern natural science, such as Bacon and Descartes,
believed that if science were to successfully minister to
human beings’ needs, it would have to alter its basic
theoretical posture. Whereas ancient science tried to
discover what things are, modern science would now
focus on how they worked. Knowledge would be seen as
desirable not for its own sake, but because it showed how
things could be manipulated to fulfill our many desires.
Consequently, modern science would effectively transform our
view of nature itself. Nature could no longer be seen as
“animated, purposive, and striving,” but as mere “dead
matter in motion,” matter that could, and should, be
mastered in order to bring about, in Bacon’s famous phrase,
“the relief of man’s estate.” The very idea of modern
science, as Kass shows, “contains manipulability at its
theoretical core.”
Biotechnology
is a variation on this larger scientific theme. But it is a
particularly dangerous variation, since it allows for the
technological manipulation of the manipulator himself.
Biotechnology thus paves the way for the complete
“medicalization of life and death.” Armed with increased
knowledge of how our genes and brains work, we are now in a
position to be the subjects of our own manipulations. This
is the deceptive promise lurking behind the biotech project.
Through neuropharmaceuticals and germ–line therapy, we are
told, we will be able to smooth out all of human nature’s
rough edges, thus making us completely at home in the world
and with ourselves.
If Kass’
diagnosis of the problem of technology is correct, and it
rings completely true to this reviewer, there is something
deeply unsettling about our current situation. The problem
of biotechnology is something that we are remarkably ill
equipped to deal with today, if for no other reason than
that we are generally unaware of the way that modern science
has shaped the very way we see ourselves and the world. What
Kass indirectly shows is that even such admirable defenders
of human dignity as Francis Fukuyama and James Q. Wilson,
who argue that the solution to the problem of biotechnology
ultimately lies in enacting sound regulations, radically
underestimate the true magnitude of the biotech challenge.
And the same could be said about those thinkers who
primarily approach the question of biotechnology from the
perspective of Pope John Paul II’s rich analysis of “the
culture of death.” As insightful and instructive as this
analysis is, it too tends to see biotechnology as the source
of some particularly dehumanizing practices and not as the
product of an all–encompassing scientific view of the world.
For liberal societies, unfortunately, there is no quick and
easy solution to the “problem” of biotechnology, precisely
because it is rooted in the very premises of the modern
scientific project itself.
Kass believes
that if we are going to confront the challenge of
biotechnology seriously and effectively we will have to
develop a “more natural biology and anthropology” than the
one we have now. Only such a “biologically informed
anthropology” can remind us of just what we have to lose
through the biotechnological transformation of our humanity.
Kass goes a long way in this book towards laying the
groundwork for such a biology—and he here builds on some of
the arguments he first made in Towards a More Natural
Science (1985). But Kass also knows that even a biology
that recognizes that human life is lived “not just
physically, but psychically, socially, and spiritually”
cannot address all of the challenges posed by the brave new
future envisioned by biotechnology. As he shows in the
book’s final chapter, “The Permanent Limitations of
Biology,” no “purely biological” account of man will ever be
able to do justice to our lived experience as human beings.
There will always be “permanent limits” to what biology can
tell us about our lives. The task of defending morality and
human dignity and of adjudicating between the claims of the
body and soul consequently will “always remain the work of a
largely autonomous ethical and political science.” A more
natural biology may be able to tell us much about “the loves
of life,” but it finally cannot tell us how we should live
with life’s different loves.
But because
he is aware of the limits of just how far biology can take
us, Kass sheds a good deal of light on what is really good
and dignified about human life. Indeed, as he points out in
a series of chapters on such biotech practices as in vitro
fertilization, organ transplantation, cloning, and
euthanasia, the cultivation of human dignity actually
requires us to live “with and against necessity, struggling
to meet it, not to overcome it.” And yet Kass is clearly no
Stoic. He sees too much good in human life to accept
Stoicism’s claim that we should always remain somewhat
detached from the world. Like Pascal and Flannery O’Connor,
he thinks that a truly human life requires us to live well
with necessity and enjoy those goods such as love and
friendship that transcend necessity—though, in contrast to
Pascal and O’Connor, there remains a tension in his thought
about how these two things finally fit together.
Kass is at
his best when reflecting on the two poles of human
biological life, birth and death. His treatment of the
“human costs” of cloning is second to none. Cutting through
the too “familiar political thickets . . . of pro–life and
pro–choice,” he shows that the new science of cloning is
emphatically not a matter of reproductive rights and
technologies. Cloning would allow us to become our own
creators, designing our descendants through the
technological tyranny of eugenics, thus making possible a
kind of evil that is even more perverse than the willful
destruction of nascent human life. This is, for Kass, the
“political” reason why we should ban human cloning—and he
makes a strong case that our initial natural “repugnance” to
cloning offers an entranceway to opening up larger questions
about the overall desirability of the biotech project.
But he also
suggests that what is most pernicious about cloning is that
it threatens to extinguish those profound erotic longings
that find their fullest expression in human coupling. For
cloning is, in principle, corrosive of the natural ties that
connect generations and the erotic desire to take part in an
act that transcends our own finite existence. The society
that condones cloning and denies “the profundity of sex,”
Kass argues, has already taken a giant step towards removing
eros from human life altogether.
Biotech’s
pursuit of what Kass calls “the immortality project”
similarly threatens our ability to live a dignified human
life. Advances in the use of human growth hormone, stem
cells, and the genetic switches that control the aging
process hold out the possibility that some day we will be
able to radically retard the aging process. But what will be
lost if death becomes an increasingly rare and remote
occurrence? What will happen to life when we will no longer
have to wonder, in the words of the Psalmist, about “the
number of our days”? Reflecting on the mysterious connection
between mortality and morality, Kass argues that awareness
of our mortality adds depth and weight to our lives and
points to the grounds of the kind of knowing self–sacrifice
that cultivates “the peculiarly human beauty of . . . virtue
and moral excellence.”
What temporal
immortality really would allow for is the endless enjoyment
of the present, a freezing of time in which we would always
have the chance to enjoy the goods life has to offer.
However, even if such a life becomes possible, it will not
bring us real happiness. “Man longs not so much for
deathlessness as for wholeness, wisdom, goodness, and
godliness.” This is, as Kass observes, the shared message of
the wisdom expressed in Aristophanes’ tale of the circle
men, Socratic philosophy, and the Bible. As Kass argues,
each of these longings—not just the desire for wisdom, as
some of Kass’ early writings suggested—points to the fact
that our desire for human wholeness cannot be satisfied by
any quantity of earthly life.
This last
observation points to the real reason why even the kind of
biology that Kass develops is finally incapable of supplying
the grounds for a wholly satisfying natural ethic. For the
truth of the matter is that the type of “wholeness” that
biblical religion speaks of is fundamentally different from
the wholeness that comes from finding our Aristophanic other
half or from the Socratic contemplation of wisdom. It is a
wholeness that embraces the good of the entire person, body
and soul, and that perfects—not smoothes out—the
imperfections of our nature. But if this is the kind of
wholeness that we really seek, we will never be truly at
home in this world, no matter how well we live with
necessity. As Peter Lawler has recently argued, perhaps
finally only theological anthropology is capable of giving a
humanly satisfying account of how we can really live well in
a world where the reach of our natural desires will always
exceed our grasp.
Marc D. Guerra teaches
theology at Assumption College in Worcester, Massachusetts.
Copyright © 2003 First Things
130 (February 2003): 59-63.
www.firstthings.com
Print
format
|