Print
format
Second Thoughts About Body Parts
Gilbert Meilaender
Almost forty thousand Americans are currently on waiting
lists, hoping to receive a donated organ. Many of
these-especially those awaiting a heart or liver
transplant-face situations that are immediately life-
threatening, and they will die if a suitable organ for
transplant is not found quickly. At the same time, about ten
thousand Americans die each year in circumstances-often
because of accidents causing severe head injuries-that make
them potential organ donors. After they have been declared
dead because of the complete cessation of brain activity, but
while heart and lung activity in the corpse is being
artifically maintained to prevent organ deterioration, both
tissues and organs- cornea, heart, lung, kidney, liver-can be
taken for transplantation.
A recent study indicated that, despite the seeming need for
organs, only about 40 percent of the ten thousand actually
become donors. In most cases the reason is that the dead
person's family refuses a request to take the organs for
transplant. If such refusal is a thoughtless act, one might
argue that we should look for new ways to persuade families to
consent to organ donation after the death of a loved one.
Thus, the death of Mickey Mantle after a liver transplantation
has been seized as the occasion for encouraging organ
donation. Many people who might never attend a talk or read a
magazine article about transplantation may be influenced by
hearing Bob Costas speak about the importance of this effort
to remember Mantle. If such refusal is not just thoughtless
but morally wrong, one might argue that we should override
it-perhaps by authorizing medical professionals routinely to
salvage, without prior request for approval, cadaver organs
for transplant. And a growing number of voices seem prepared
to argue for such a policy. If such refusal is motivated by
concerns that are selfish or, at least, self- regarding, one
might argue that we should fight fire with fire by offering to
compensate the family for donated organs-appealing to their
self-regarding impulses in order to achieve desirable social
aims. And such arguments continue to get a hearing in our
society.
On the other hand, if weighty-albeit often
unarticulated-reasons may underlie such refusals, we ought to
be very skeptical about the increasing social pressure to
encourage organ donation and transplantation. These are not
just questions of public policy. They are also questions that
pit our deep-seated hunger to live longer and our fear of
death against equally deep-seated notions of the sacredness of
human life in the body. In what follows I consider the
road we have traveled in making our peace with organ donation
and transplantation. Without rejecting that road entirely, I
aim to reflect upon its ambiguities and upon what Christians
in particular might now say about such "progress." Our
rhetoric has generally favored organ donation, but we must
learn to be circumspect in the use of such rhetoric.
I
In the late 1960s the Uniform Anatomical Gift Act was
passed into law in every state in this country. It allows
individuals, while still living, to authorize the donation of
any parts of their body after death. If the deceased person
had not authorized such donation but also had not prohibited
it, specified family members are permitted to give
authorization. The National Organ Transplantation Act, passed
by Congress in 1984, established a national registry and
donor-recipient matching system while also prohibiting the
sale of organs for transplant. Some states have, in addition,
passed laws requiring medical personnel to ask the family of
the deceased to donate his or her organs. Thus, we have given
social approval to a system in which needed organs are donated
but not to systems in which they are routinely taken without
permission or sold as commodities on the open market.
Nevertheless, this system of giving and receiving has not
provided as many donated organs as are desired for transplant
purposes.
On some occasions organs are given by living donors,
but this can be permitted only within clear limits. Years ago
Paul Ramsey called attention to one of those limits,
recounting the following fictitious case study:
Many months ago the fifteen-year-old son of Mr. Roger
Johnson was admitted to a Houston, Texas hospital for tests
to determine the cause of his generally debilitated
condition. Use of the latest available diagnostic techniques
and equipment eventually led to the conclusion that the lad
was suffering from a progressively deteriorating congenital
condition of the valves of the heart. The prognosis
communicated to the distraught Mr. Johnson was that his son
could not live past the age of twenty, and that there was no
known treatment for the malady with which he was
afflicted.
At first Mr. Johnson tried to resign himself to his son's
plight. Then he began to brood and think of the pleasures
and joys of adult life which he, at the age of forty-two,
had already known, but which his son would never know. The
more he thought of this, the less willing he became
passively to accept the doctors' verdict. Finally he thought
of a means by which his son's life might be
spared.
His plan, which he communicated to a physician friend,
was an uncomplicated one. In light of the success of recent
heart transplant operations with unrelated donors and
donees, he reasoned, there must be a high probability that a
transplant of the heart of a genetic relative would be
successful. Accordingly, he would simply donate his own
heart to his son. He had lived a full life, he said, and he
could leave his son well provided for financially. His wife
had died several years earlier, so that complication was not
present. His own parents had no rightful claim to his
continued life. He asked his friend's aid in finding a
physician who would perform the operation. Not without
considerable misgivings, his friend complied, eventually
finding a heart surgeon eager to attempt the transplant of a
heart from a healthy and related donor not in extremis at
the time of the operation.
In the course of preparation for the transplant,
elaborate precaution was taken to ensure that the son would
not know the real nature of the proposed operation. He was
told simply that a transplant operation on his heart was to
be attempted in the hope of prolonging his life, and he
agreed to try it with full knowledge that death could
certainly result if the try were unsuccessful. In reality,
of course, it was contemplated that Mr. Johnson's heart
would be removed from his chest while he was under general
anaesthesia and that it would be transplanted in the chest
cavity of his son.
When the date of the scheduled operation arrived, the
father went to the son's room, affectionately wished him
good luck, and returned to his own room to be prepared for
his own operation. He was eventually placed under general
anaesthesia, and taken to a special operating room to await
the transfer of his heart to an oxygenating and circulating
"heart-lung" machine.
He is in the operating room now, and the surgeon is
scrubbing. You are chief of staff in the hospital in which
the operation is to take place. You had no prior knowledge
of the operation, but this is frequently so. A worried nurse
has brought you word of the planned operation on this
occasion. You have power to stop the operation. Should you
do it?
The case is striking because it makes clear what Christian
rhetoric about "love" and "freedom" sometimes blurs: Not every
gift can properly be given by those who know themselves to be
creatures rather than Creator. The body, as the place of
personal presence, has its own integrity, which ought to be
respected. Indeed, because we are regarded as stewards rather
than owners of our bodily life, the Roman Catholic and Jewish
traditions generally forbade self-mutilation. These traditions
have become willing to approve the self-giving of organs or
tissues for transplantation as long as the donation will not
cause grave harm to the donor's bodily life. Certainly any
organ donation-such as that of heart, liver, or lung-that
would cause death or great harm to a living donor is not a
proper work of creaturely love. (Interestingly, an
increasingly secular society, in which many people do not
share Christian and Jewish disapproval of suicide, may find it
hard to explain why such donations should be forbidden or why
the case study recounted from Ramsey should remain
fictitious.)
In general, therefore, we may regard donation of a kidney
or of bone marrow as significantly different from donation of
heart, lung, or liver. (In recent years partial grafts of
liver and lung tissue, which do not involve transplantation of
the entire organ, have been attempted. To the degree these
procedures are successful, our evaluation of them will, no
doubt, be similar to our evalution of bone marrow donation.)
Yet, a living donor's gift even of tissue or a paired organ
(such as the kidney) should not be approved without careful
reflection. Doctors have in the past been hesitant to
transplant kidneys from living, unrelated donors, and
it is good that they should be. We should want them to be
reluctant to subject a healthy person to the risks of a major
operation and the loss of one kidney even if that person is
eager to make this bodily gift. It is true, of course, that we
ought always be ready to risk harm to ourselves for the sake
of others. But it is one thing to aim at my neighbor's good,
knowing that in so doing I may be harmed; it is another to aim
at my own harm in order to do good to my neighbor. We
need not oppose all organ donation from living donors, but
neither should we regard such cases as morally uncomplicated.
In recent years the number of kidney donations from living
unrelated donors has increased. In part this has been
due to a growing willingness to accept donation from the
spouse of a patient suffering from kidney disease, but there
have also been cases of such donations between friends or
even, simply, acquaintances. Because the increased willingness
to permit such donations is due in part to the pressure for
organs and the desire of transplant surgeons to do what they
can to meet that need, we must beware of the tyranny of the
possible-the pressure to suppose that we are obligated to
do whatever we are able to do. Bioethicists generally worry
that unrelated donors might be pressured or paid, or that
spouses might feel a kind of pressure that keeps their consent
from being truly free.
No doubt such concerns are legitimate and are worth our
attention. Consent is not the only important moral issue,
however, and those worries ought not obscure an even larger
underlying issue: the integrity of bodily life. If we learn to
regard our bodies simply as collections of organs potentially
useful to others, we are in danger of losing any close
connection between the person and the body. That connection
has always been affirmed in Christian thought, although it has
often been a fragile connection. We are regularly tempted to
suppose that the "real" person transcends the body, and, when
we do, dehumanization lies near at hand. An acute sense of
that dehumanizing tendency to regard our bodies as collections
of alienable parts moved Leon Kass to refer to organ
transplantation as "simply a noble form of cannibalism." That
striking phrase is not overdone as long we take the whole of
it seriously. Not just cannibalism, but noble
cannibalism. Kass would not have us ignore the nobility
involved in gifts of the body, but neither would he have us
think too casually about the body's own integrity and its
meaning as the place of personal presence.
Because of reservations about organs given by living
donors, the tendency in transplantation (since the discovery
of drugs to suppress the body's immune reaction that rejects
foreign tissue) has been to use cadaver organs taken
immediately after death. (This assumes, of course, that the
deceased had, while still living, authorized such donation, or
that appropriate family members have done so after his death.)
And, of course, from a cadaver one can take for transplant not
only a paired organ such as the kidney but unpaired organs
such as the heart. Is there any reason not to approve such
donations? Is there, in fact, any reason why Christians should
not be encouraged to make such gifts of the body?
We should note first that here too a certain caution is in
order. Given the increasing pressure to make more organs
available for transplant, we will see a growing tendency to
think of cadaver organs as a communal resource available for
the taking-unless perhaps the family of the deceased objects.
That tendency ignores the human significance of burial and a
family's desire to take leave of a loved one. William F. May
once noted that it is "wrong, indecorous, and enraging" to
force a family "to claim the body as its possession,
only in order to proceed with rites in the course of which it
must acknowledge the process of surrender and separation." May
recalled a tale from the Brothers Grimm in which a young man
who is incapable of horror and does not shrink back from the
dead attempts even to play with a corpse and is sent away "to
learn how to shudder." If families are often reluctant to
authorize organ donation after the death of a loved one, that
reluctance ought to be honored-lest we collectively forget how
to shudder. Indeed, I do not think it wise even to act upon
the deceased person's previously stated willingness to be a
donor in the face of family reluctance or objection. Our
society's desperate attempt to find ways to live longer should
not be allowed to override a deep-seated and difficult to
articulate sense of the importance of the body, even the dead
body.
II
When cyclosporine, the first powerful immunosuppressive
drug, was discovered in 1972, transplantation technology was
revolutionized. If the immune system's rejection of an alien
organ could be overcome, the possibilities seemed endless. No
longer would transplants be conceivable only if donor and
recipient were closely enough related to be a good match. And
once donation from strangers became reasonable to contemplate,
it also became possible to move beyond living donors' gifts of
paired vital organs (such as a kidney) to transplantation of
unpaired vital organs (such as the heart or liver) from
cadaver donors. But the crucial conceptual notion here is that
of "brain death."
In 1968 an ad hoc committee at Harvard recommended a
neurological criterion-cessation of brain activity-for
determining death. Prior to that, cessation of heart and lung
activity-a cardiopulmonary criterion- had been generally used
to mark the point of death. But it had by then become possible
to sustain heart and lung activity (with a respirator) for
days or even weeks after a patient had irreversibly lost all
brain function. Therefore, the two traditional "vital signs"
of heart and lung activity could be maintained solely through
mechanical assistance. In these circumstances it made sense to
many to say that a human being actually dies when brain
activity ends, because only that activity makes possible the
body's ability to function as an integrated whole.
The Harvard committee attempted simply to fix criteria on
the basis of which physicians could determine that a patient
was neurologically dead. Its criteria-including lack of
responsiveness, no breathing or movement (when off the
respirator), no reflexes, and a flat EEG-have been largely
accepted and written into law in the years since then. The
Harvard criteria were intended to determine when all
brain activity had ended, when "whole brain" death had
occurred. A person can, of course, suffer the loss of "higher"
brain (cortical) function, losing the capacities for awareness
or self-consciousness, while brain stem functions (controlling
spontaneous breathing, eye-opening, etc.) remain. According to
the Harvard criteria, loss of higher brain functions alone did
not constitute death, and the laws of our states that have
established criteria for determining brain death have had
whole brain death in view.
We have learned, then, to think of death as a single
phenomenon whose presence is indicated either by
irreversible loss of heart and lung function (the traditional
criterion) or by irreversible loss of all brain
function. This is not unreasonable, but the concept of "brain
death" remains conceptually and experientially puzzling in
some ways. It permits transplant surgeons to retrieve the
organs of a neurologically dead person while, because of
mechanical assistance, circulation of oxygenated blood
sustains the vitality of those organs in the "corpse." Yet, of
course, even if we agreed that irreversible loss of whole
brain function established that the person was dead, we would
be reluctant to bury a corpse until its heart had ceased to
beat. We seem willing, therefore, to remove organs for
transplant from a corpse before we would be willing to bury
it. The body has died, because it can no longer function as an
integrated whole; yet, with mechanical assistance some organs
and tissues, taken by themselves, retain vitality. If that
makes us uneasy, we might prefer to remove mechanical
assistance and let the body die "all the way." But then, of
course, its organs are unlikely to be usable for
transplantation.
More than a quarter century ago, when this move to "update"
criteria for determining death began, it was met with
suspicion. At that time the technology of transplant surgery
was beginning to make progress, and some people suspected that
the desire to establish in law a concept of brain death was
motivated only by the wish to obtain organs for transplant
before those organs had deteriorated (as they will rapidly
when heart and lung activity fail). In truth, however, there
were other reasons-apart from the desire for transplantable
organs-to rethink the criteria for determining death, since
one needed to decide whether a respirator was simply
oxygenating a corpse or sustaining a living human being.
The suspicions may not have been entirely groundless,
however-or, perhaps better, they may have been ahead of their
time. For it has become clear in recent years that the thirst
for transplantable organs is so strong that we are, in fact,
tempted to redefine death in order to secure the "needed"
organs. For example, in 1994 the Council on Ethical and
Judicial Affairs of the American Medical Association issued an
opinion holding that it is "ethically permissible" to use "the
anencephalic neonate" as an organ donor, even though, as the
Council recognized, under current law anencephalic babies are
not dead. Anencephaly is a condition in which an infant is
born with a fully or partially functioning brain stem but
without any cerebral hemispheres (higher brain). These infants
can never have any awareness of their own existence or of the
surroundings in which they live, and they usually die within
hours or days. With aggressive treatment it may on occasion be
possible to sustain their life somewhat longer, but, because
they are essentially dying patients, it seems better simply to
give them what care and comfort we can while permitting them
to die without the bodily intrusiveness of aggressive
measures.
It is worth noting that as recently as 1988 the AMA's
Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs had concluded that it
was not permissible to remove organs for
transplantation from anencephalic infants while they were
still alive, even though it is harder to maintain organs in
suitable condition if one waits until the infant has sustained
whole brain death. The Council's 1994 opinion is quite frankly
based on a sense that it is imperative to acquire organs for
transplant.
Newborns and other young children usually can benefit
from organ transplants only if the organs are taken from
children of similar size. However, there is a serious
shortage of pediatric organ donors. As a result, each year
approximately five hundred children need heart transplants,
another five hundred need liver replacements, and
approximately four hundred to five hundred children in the
United States need kidney transplants. With the scarcity of
hearts, livers, and kidneys available for transplantation,
30 percent to 50 percent of children on the transplant
waiting list die while waiting for a suitable organ. These
figures are undoubtedly underestimates of the shortage of
pediatric organs. With the long waiting lists for the
organs, many children in need never make it onto the lists
because they would not have high enough priority to receive
an organ or because they do not live long enough to have
their names entered on the waiting list.
For these reasons the Council in 1994 approved what we
would ordinarily regard as wrong. Normally, an unpaired vital
organ such as the heart could be taken for transplant only
from a cadaver donor (who had previously consented or
whose family had consented). But within only six years the
Council reversed its earlier position and approved such
"donations" from anencephalic infants-approved, we should not
hesitate to say, taking the life of these infants in order to
make their organs available for transplant to other children
whose life prospects are better. "Permitting such organ
donation," the Council suggested, "would allow some good to
come from a truly tragic situation, sustaining the lives of
other children and providing psychological relief for those
parents who wish to give meaning to the short life of the
anencephalic neonate."
It happens that in December 1995, the AMA's Council, under
considerable pressure from its House of Delegates, once more
reversed direction and rescinded its 1994 opinion permitting
organ donation from living anencephalic infants. It did so,
however, only on the ground that doubt had arisen whether all
anencephalic infants lack consciousness and whether an assured
diagnosis of anencephaly is always possible. If, therefore,
further study demonstrates that these infants do lack
consciousness and that their condition can be reliably
diagnosed, the Council would have no reason not to change
direction one more time and approve the use of living
anencephalic infants as organ donors.
This is the sort of slippery slope on which we stand if we
permit ourselves to believe that ours is the godlike
responsibility of bringing good out of every human tragedy. We
suppose that ours is the task of giving "meaning" to a child's
life, and we permit ourselves to use the infant's death as a
means of psychological relief for others. Moreover, we will
gradually learn to think of ourselves and others not as living
beings whose bodies have their own unity and integrity but, in
Paul Ramsey's words, as "ensembles of parts . . . to be given
away or taken or-worst of all-sold." We are on the way to
seeing ourselves, in Ramsey's arresting phrase, as "a useful
precadaver." That I do not exaggerate can be seen from recent
discussions about procuring organs for transplant from what
are called "non-heart-beating cadavers."
As I noted above, most organs for transplant come today
from cadaver donors who have been declared brain dead but
whose hearts are still beating because of mechanical
assistance. Because the supply of donor organs does not meet
demand, however, the search is always on for new sources of
organs. At the University of Pittsburgh Medical Center, a
major center of transplant surgery, that search has recently
focused on non-heart-beating cadaver donors. These are
patients who have been declared dead by traditional
cardiopulmonary criteria after they or their families have
decided to forgo any further treatments. After the decision to
forgo further life-sustaining treatment has been made, the
still living person is taken to the operating room. There
therapy is withdrawn, the patient dies on the operating table,
and his organs are removed immediately after death is
declared.
Objecting to this on a variety of grounds, Renee Fox, a
sociologist whose pioneering studies of transplant technology
are well known, has singled out as "most dreadful" what she
terms "the desolate, profanely 'high tech' death that the
patient/donor dies, beneath operating room lights, amidst
masked, gowned, and gloved strangers, who have prepared [the]
body for the eviscerating surgery that will follow." Perhaps
if our noble desire to prolong life leads us to such ignoble
means, we need to be sent away to learn how to shudder.
Rather than shuddering, it is of course possible to forge
boldly ahead. If the Pittsburgh Protocol for obtaining organs
seems almost to mock the view that unpaired vital organs
should be taken only after the donor has died-to mock it, that
is, by adhering to the letter but not the spirit- we might
instead simply abandon the claim that it is always necessary
to wait for death before procuring organs for transplant.
Without recommending it, Robert Arnold and Stuart Youngner
describe what this might mean.
Machine-dependent patients could give consent for organ
removal before they are dead. For example, a
ventilator-dependent ALS patient could request that life
support be removed at 5:00 p.m., but that at 9:00 a.m. the
same day he be taken to the operating room, put under
general anesthesia, and his kidneys, liver, and pancreas
removed. Bleeding vessels would be tied off or cauterized.
The patient's heart would not be removed and would continue
to beat throughout the surgery, perfusing the other organs
with warm, oxygen- and nutrient-rich blood until they were
removed. The heart would stop, and the patient would be
pronounced dead only after the ventilator was removed at
5:00 p.m., according to plan, and long before the patient
could die from renal, hepatic, or pancreatic
failure.
If active euthanasia-e.g., lethal injection-and
physician-assisted suicide are legally sanctioned, even more
patients could couple organ donation with their planned
deaths; we would not have to depend only upon persons
attached to life support. This practice would yield not only
more donors, but more types of organs as well, since the
heart could now be removed from dying, not just dead,
patients.
Arnold and Youngner do not, as I noted, claim that we
should turn in this direction, but they view it as an honest
projection of where we may gradually be headed.
In recent years we have also seen stories of children
conceived in order to serve as bone marrow donors for
family members. Increasingly, some argue that we should permit
the sale and purchase of organs needed for transplant-that, in
this way at least, the body may be a commodity for sale.
Having set foot on the path of transplantation, we seem unable
to find any exit ramp as we press toward a vision of humanity
in which everyone becomes "a useful precadaver."
Can our public policy find an exit ramp? Not unless we
first recover it for ourselves. The truth is, we will do
almost anything to keep ourselves or our loved ones alive.
Whatever we may think public policy ought to be, if our own
life or our child's were at stake, we might well bend our
entire energies to the task of finding an organ for
transplant. Whatever could be done we would be tempted to do,
and we are therefore helpless in the face of the relentless
advance of this technology. Christians, who know that death is
indeed an evil and the last enemy opposed to God's will for
the creation, should find the temptation quite
understandable.
But we also need to develop the trust and the courage that
will enable us sometimes to decline to do what medical
technology makes possible. There are circumstances in which we
can save life-even our own or that of a loved one-only by
destroying the kind of world in which we all should want to
live. In learning to say no, in becoming people who give
thanks for medical progress but do not worship it or place our
trust in it, we may bear a different kind of life-giving
witness to our world.
Gilbert Meilaender is Professor of Religion at Oberlin
College. His new book, Body, Soul, and Bioethics, has
just been published by the University of Notre Dame Press.
Copyright © 1996 First Things 62 (April 1996): 32-37.
www.firstthings.com
Print
format
|